Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 24
Filter
Add more filters










Publication year range
1.
Ethics Int Aff ; 35(4): 543-562, 2021.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34937990

ABSTRACT

COVID-19 vaccines are likely to be scarce for years to come. Many countries, from India to the U.K., have demonstrated vaccine nationalism. What are the ethical limits to this vaccine nationalism? Neither extreme nationalism nor extreme cosmopolitanism is ethically justifiable. Instead, we propose the fair priority for residents (FPR) framework, in which governments can retain COVID-19 vaccine doses for their residents only to the extent that they are needed to maintain a noncrisis level of mortality while they are implementing reasonable public health interventions. Practically, a noncrisis level of mortality is that experienced during a bad influenza season, which society considers an acceptable background risk. Governments take action to limit mortality from influenza, but there is no emergency that includes severe lockdowns. This "flu-risk standard" is a nonarbitrary and generally accepted heuristic. Mortality above the flu-risk standard justifies greater governmental interventions, including retaining vaccines for a country's own citizens over global need. The precise level of vaccination needed to meet the flu-risk standard will depend upon empirical factors related to the pandemic. This links the ethical principles to the scientific data emerging from the emergency. Thus, the FPR framework recognizes that governments should prioritize procuring vaccines for their country when doing so is necessary to reduce mortality to noncrisis flu-like levels. But after that, a government is obligated to do its part to share vaccines to reduce risks of mortality for people in other countries. We consider and reject objections to the FPR framework based on a country: (1) having developed a vaccine, (2) raising taxes to pay for vaccine research and purchase, (3) wanting to eliminate economic and social burdens, and (4) being ineffective in combating COVID-19 through public health interventions.

4.
J Med Ethics ; 39(4): 195-204, 2013 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22194319

ABSTRACT

Biodefence, broadly understood as efforts to prevent or mitigate the damage of a bioterrorist attack, raises a number of ethical issues, from the allocation of scarce biomedical research and public health funds, to the use of coercion in quarantine and other containment measures in the event of an outbreak. In response to the US bioterrorist attacks following September 11, significant US policy decisions were made to spur scientific enquiry in the name of biodefence. These decisions led to a number of critical institutional changes within the US federal government agencies governing scientific research. Subsequent science policy discussions have focused largely on 'the dual use problem': how to preserve the openness of scientific research while preventing research undertaken for the prevention or mitigation of biological threats from third parties. We join others in shifting the ethical debate over biodefence away from a simple framing of the problem as one of dual use, by demonstrating how a dual use framing distorts the debate about bioterrorism and truncates discussion of the moral issues. We offer an alternative framing rooted in social epistemology and institutional design theory, arguing that the ethical and policy debates regarding 'dual use' biomedical research ought to be reframed as a larger optimisation problem across a plurality of values including, among others: (1) the production of scientific knowledge; (2) the protection of human and animal subjects; (3) the promotion and protection of public health (national and global); (4) freedom of scientific enquiry; and (5) the constraint of government power.


Subject(s)
Academies and Institutes , Access to Information , Biomedical Research/ethics , Bioterrorism/prevention & control , Freedom , Government Agencies , Knowledge , Public Health , Research Subjects , Security Measures/standards , Academies and Institutes/ethics , Advisory Committees , Animals , Biomedical Research/standards , Biomedical Research/trends , Computer Security/standards , Ethics, Research , Global Health , Humans , Public Policy , Security Measures/trends , Social Responsibility , Social Values , United States
5.
J Med Ethics ; 38(3): 140-1, 2012 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22138729

ABSTRACT

David DeGrazia's article provides a careful and fair rendition of my position on the possibility of post-persons. However, I am unconvinced that he has shown that such beings are possible. My view is based on two assumptions: (1) the concept of moral status is a threshold concept; and (2) the most plausible understanding of moral status as a threshold concept is a Kantian respect-based view, according to which all and only those beings who have the capacity to be accountable for reasons have the high status we associate with persons. I argue that the superior beings DeGrazia describes would be more morally admirable than us, but would not have a higher moral status. I also argue that, contrary to DeGrazia, even the most intelligent of canines do not have the capacity for accountability for reasons, even in an attenuated form. I then argue that DeGrazia faces a painful dilemma: either he must give up the assumption that moral status (so far as persons are concerned) is a threshold concept and say that for any two beings with the capacity for accountability for reasons, the one with the greater capacity has a higher moral status; or he must retain the view that moral status is a threshold concept but concede that he has not account of where the threshold lies.


Subject(s)
Genetic Enhancement/ethics , Morals , Animals , Humans
6.
J Med Philos ; 36(1): 6-27, 2011 Feb.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21228084

ABSTRACT

Many philosophers invoke the "wisdom of nature" in arguing for varying degrees of caution in the development and use of genetic enhancement technologies. Because they view natural selection as akin to a master engineer that creates functionally and morally optimal design, these authors tend to regard genetic intervention with suspicion. In Part II, we examine and ultimately reject the evolutionary assumptions that underlie the master engineer analogy (MEA). By highlighting the constraints on ordinary unassisted evolution, we show how intentional genetic modification can overcome many of the natural impediments to the human good. Our contention is that genetic engineering offers a solution that is more eff icient, reliable, versatile, and morally palatable than the lumbering juggernaut of Darwinian evolution. In Part III, we evaluate a recent attempt to ground precautionary enhancement heuristics in adaptive etiology. Our problem with this approach is two-fold: first, it is based on the same "strong adaptationist" interpretation of evolution that motivates the flawed MEA, and second, the etiological concept of function on which it relies provides indirect and potentially misleading information about the likely consequences of genetic intervention. We offer instead enhancement criteria based on causal relationships in ontogeny. We conclude that rather than grounding a presumption against deliberate genetic modification, the causal structure of the living world gives us good moral reason to pursue it.


Subject(s)
Biological Evolution , Genetic Enhancement/ethics , Adaptation, Biological , Animals , Evolution, Molecular , Humans , Philosophy, Medical , Quality of Life
7.
Bioethics ; 23(3): 141-50, 2009 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19161567

ABSTRACT

Appeals to the idea of human nature are frequent in the voluminous literature on the ethics of enhancing human beings through biotechnology. Two chief concerns about the impact of enhancements on human nature have been voiced. The first is that enhancement may alter or destroy human nature. The second is that if enhancement alters or destroys human nature, this will undercut our ability to ascertain the good because, for us, the good is determined by our nature. The first concern assumes that altering or destroying human nature is in itself a bad thing. The second concern assumes that human nature provides a standard without which we cannot make coherent, defensible judgments about what is good. I will argue (1) that there is nothing wrong, per se, with altering or destroying human nature, because, on a plausible understanding of what human nature is, it contains bad as well as good characteristics and there is no reason to believe that eliminating some of the bad would so imperil the good as to make the elimination of the bad impermissible, and (2) that altering or destroying human nature need not result in the loss of our ability to make judgments about the good, because we possess a conception of the good by which we can and do evaluate human nature. I will argue that appeals to human nature tend to obscure rather than illuminate the debate over the ethics of enhancement and can be eliminated in favor of more cogent considerations.


Subject(s)
Biomedical Enhancement/ethics , Human Characteristics , Philosophy , Humans
8.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 18(1): 1-34, 2008 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-18561576

ABSTRACT

Much of the debate about the ethics of enhancement has proceeded according to two framing assumptions. The first is that although enhancement carries large social risks, the chief benefits of enhancement are to those who are enhanced (or their parents, in the case of enhancing the traits of children). The second is that, because we now understand the wrongs of state-driven eugenics, enhancements, at least in liberal societies, will be personal goods, chosen or not chosen in a market for enhancement services. This article argues that both framing assumptions must be rejected, once it is understood that some enhancements--especially those that are most likely to garner resources and become widespread--will increase human productivity. Once one appreciates the productivity-increasing potential of enhancements, one can begin to see that enhancement need not be primarily a zero sum affair, that the social costs of forgoing enhancements may be great, and that the state may well take an interest in facilitating biomedical enhancements, just as it does in facilitating education and other productivity-increasing traditional enhancements. Appreciating the productivity-increasing potential of enhancements also makes it possible to view the enhancement debate in a new light, through the lens of the ethics of development.


Subject(s)
Child, Gifted , Efficiency , Genetic Enhancement/ethics , Human Characteristics , Human Development , Biomedical Enhancement/ethics , Child , Efficiency/ethics , Eugenics , Humans , Moral Obligations , Social Change , Social Planning
9.
Theor Med Bioeth ; 27(1): 95-114, 2006.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16532305

ABSTRACT

There are several reasons for the current prominence of global health issues. Among the most important is the growing awareness that some risks to health are global in scope and can only be countered by global cooperation. In addition, human rights discourse and, more generally, the articulation of a coherent cosmopolitan ethical perspective that acknowledges the importance of all persons, regardless of where they live, provide a normative basis for taking global health seriously as a moral issue. In this paper we begin the task of translating the vague commitment to doing something to improve global health into a coherent set of more determinate obligations. One chief conclusion of our inquiry is that the responsibilities of states regarding global health are both more determinate and more extensive than is usually assumed. We also argue, however, that institutional innovation will be needed to achieve a more comprehensive, fair distribution of concrete responsibilities regarding global health and to provide effective mechanisms for holding various state and nonstate actors accountable for fulfilling them.


Subject(s)
Global Health , Government , Health Policy , Human Rights , International Cooperation , Public Health , Social Justice , Social Responsibility , Developed Countries , Developing Countries , Drug Industry/economics , Drug Industry/ethics , Humans , Organizational Policy , Private Sector
10.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 12(1): 1-15, 2002 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-12211263

ABSTRACT

Pharmacogenetics offers the prospect of an era of safer and more effective drugs, as well as more individualized use of drug therapies. Before the benefits of pharmacogenetics can be realized, the ethical issues that arise in research and clinical application of pharmacogenetic technologies must be addressed. The ethical issues raised by pharmacogenetics can be addressed under six headings: (1) regulatory oversight, (2) confidentiality and privacy, (3) informed consent, (4) availability of drugs, (5) access, and (6) clinicians' changing responsibilities in the era of pharmacogenetic medicine. We analyze each of these categories of ethical issues and provide policy approaches for addressing them.


Subject(s)
Genetic Research , Genetic Testing , Pharmacogenetics , Confidentiality , Drug Industry , Genetic Privacy , Genetic Testing/legislation & jurisprudence , Genetic Variation , Government Regulation , Humans , Informed Consent , Insurance, Health , Physician's Role , Public Policy , Risk Assessment , United States , United States Food and Drug Administration
11.
Health Aff (Millwood) ; 21(4): 155-67, 2002.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-12117126

ABSTRACT

Pharmacogenetics--the effect of genotype on drug response--holds the promise of safer and more effective drug therapy. Genetic tests would be routinely given to patients prior to prescription of a drug, with therapeutic decisions based on the patient's drug-response profile. This paper examines the operational changes and the ethical, legal, and policy challenges that pharmacogenetic medicine poses for key actors in the health care system. Adaptation by drug companies, regulatory agencies, physicians, patients, insurers, and public funding agencies will be necessary to integrate pharmacogenetic medicine into health care.


Subject(s)
Delivery of Health Care , Pharmacogenetics , Drug Industry/organization & administration , Education, Medical , Financing, Government , Genetic Testing , Humans , Pharmacogenetics/economics , Pharmacogenetics/legislation & jurisprudence , Pharmacogenetics/organization & administration , Privacy , United States
13.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 10(3): 189-212, 2000 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11658207

ABSTRACT

Two basic criticisms of managed care are that it erodes patient trust in physicians and subjects physicians to incentives and pressures that compromise the physician's fiduciary obligation to the patient. In this article, I first distinguish between status trust and merit trust, and then argue (1) that the value of status trust in physicians is probably over-rated and certainly underdocumented; (2) that erosion of status trust may not be detrimental if accompanied by an increase in well-founded merit trust; and (3) that under conditions of managed care the physician's commitment to traditional medical ethics cannot serve as an adequate basis for merit trust. Next, drawing on an analogy between managed care organzations and politics, I argue that (4) the most appropriate basis for merit trust in managed care is a conception of organizational legitimacy that includes procedural justice, empowerment of constructive criticism within the organization, and organizational accommodation of the noninstrumental commitment to patient well-being that is distinctive of medical professionalism. I then explore the conditions necessary for robust competition for merit trust among managed care organizations and indicate the kinds of public policies needed to facilitate such competition. Finally, I show how the account of organization-based merit trust can accommodate the special fiduciary obligation of medical professionals, without indulging in the delusion that it is the physician's fiduciary obligation always to provide all care that is expected to be of any net benefit to the patient.


Subject(s)
Ethics, Institutional , Managed Care Programs , Physician-Patient Relations , Trust , Cost-Benefit Analysis , Disclosure , Economics , Ethics, Medical , Humans , Managed Competition , Moral Obligations , Motivation , Organizational Policy , Patient Advocacy , Patients , Physicians , Politics , Public Policy , Social Control, Informal , Social Justice , Social Responsibility , United States
14.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 6(3): 245-50, 1996 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11653396

ABSTRACT

The mandate of the U.S. Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Experiments required that the Committee take a position on the validity of retrospective moral judgments. However, throughout its period of operation, the Committee remained divided on the question of whether sound judgments of individual culpability and wrongdoing should be included in its Final Report. This essay examines the arguments that various committee members marshalled to support their opposing views on retrospective moral judgment and explains the significance of the controversy.


Subject(s)
Advisory Committees , Ethical Analysis , Ethical Review , Ethics , Human Experimentation , Morals , Public Policy , Radiation , Retrospective Moral Judgment , Scientific Misconduct , Compensation and Redress , Dissent and Disputes , Economics , Ethics, Medical , Evaluation Studies as Topic , Federal Government , Government , Group Processes , History , History, 20th Century , Human Rights , Humans , Moral Obligations , Organizational Policy , Politics , Reference Standards , Research Personnel , Research Subjects , Social Justice , Social Responsibility , United States
16.
Bioethics ; 9(3-4): 220-39, 1995 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11653038

ABSTRACT

When advocates of insurance-privatization consider whether private insurance-dominated systems achieve justice at all, they tend to rely on an incomplete set of criteria for a just healthcare system. They also mistakenly assume that it is enough to show that justice is in principle achievable within a private insurance-dominated system. This essay offers a more complete set of criteria for a just healthcare system. It then argues that the motivational assumptions needed to make insurance-privatization at all plausible (on grounds of choice, efficiency, and quality of care) are inconsistent with the motivational assumptions needed to show that in practice a private insurance-dominated system will achieve justice. A private insurance-dominated system can be expected to satisfy the criteria for just healthcare only if (a) there is extensive and effective regulation to constrain the normal competitive behavior of private insurers or if (b) generous public funds are provided to fill the gaps in access left by the private insurance market. Yet the assumptions about the motivations and abilities of the public, regulators, and public officials needed to satisfy conditions (a) or (b) contradict the privatization advocate's explanations of how privatization will maximize efficiency, choice, and quality of care.


Subject(s)
Delivery of Health Care , Industry , Insurance, Health , Private Sector , Public Policy , Social Justice , Socioeconomic Factors , Altruism , Biomedical Research , Developing Countries , Education, Medical , Federal Government , Financing, Government , Genetic Diseases, Inborn , Goals , Government , Government Regulation , Health Care Rationing , Health Care Reform , Humans , Insurance Selection Bias , Physicians , Policy Making , Politics , Poverty , Prejudice , Public Sector , Quality of Health Care , Research , Resource Allocation , Social Control, Formal , United States
18.
Bioethics ; 2(4): 317-33, 1988 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11651923

ABSTRACT

KIE: Principal/agent theory, an economics concept that defines an agency relationship as "a contract under which one or more persons engage another person (the agent) to perform some service on their behalf which involves delegating some decision-making authority to the agent," is held to be applicable to the patient/physician relationship, in contrast to the view that this is a fiduciary relationship, not a contractual one. The distinction between fiduciary and contractual relationships is illuminated in the process of evaluating objections to the application of the principal/agent theory to the patient/physician relationship. The ability of the principal/agent theory to reveal important features of advance directives, understood as public documents rather than as confidential instructions from patient to physician, is also examined.^ieng


Subject(s)
Advance Directives , Decision Making , Delivery of Health Care , Economics , Freedom , Paternalism , Patient Participation , Personal Autonomy , Physician-Patient Relations , Physicians , Advance Directive Adherence , Conflict of Interest , Contracts , Cost-Benefit Analysis , Euthanasia, Passive , Family , Fees and Charges , Humans , Industry , Information Dissemination , Information Services , Insurance, Health , Living Wills , Motivation , Professional Competence , Public Policy , Social Justice , Third-Party Consent , Trust
19.
Philos Public Aff ; 17(4): 277-302, 1988.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11657368

ABSTRACT

KIE: The value and authority of advance directives such as the living will and the durable power of attorney are discussed, as well as the dangers of loss of personal identity and psychological continuity that these directives present. Differing theories of the degree of psychological continuity necessary for the preservation of personal identity are examined, concluding with the author's "compromise position" that cases of permanent unconsciousness and neurological dementia destroy some of the preconditions for personhood and thereby negate the choice between respecting the wishes of the formerly competent person and the new, different person's life because such beings are not persons at all.^ieng


Subject(s)
Advance Directive Adherence , Advance Directives , Brain Diseases , Brain Injuries , Dementia , Ethics , Euthanasia, Passive , Human Rights , Individuality , Life Support Care , Mental Competency , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Reference Standards , Right to Die , Self Concept , Social Responsibility , Age Factors , Altruism , Decision Making , Freedom , Humans , Living Wills , Paternalism , Persistent Vegetative State , Personal Autonomy , Philosophy , Psychology , Third-Party Consent , Time Factors , Treatment Refusal
20.
Bioethics ; 2(4): 317-333, 1988 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28872222
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...