Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 33
Filter
1.
J Med Philos ; 49(3): 313-323, 2024 Apr 20.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38538066

ABSTRACT

The controversy over the equivalence of continuous sedation until death (CSD) and physician-assisted suicide/euthanasia (PAS/E) provides an opportunity to focus on a significant extended use of CSD. This extension, suggested by the equivalence of PAS/E and CSD, is designed to promote additional patient autonomy at the end-of-life. Samuel LiPuma, in his article, "Continuous Sedation Until Death as Physician-Assisted Suicide/Euthanasia: A Conceptual Analysis" claims equivalence between CSD and death; his paper is seminal in the equivalency debate. Critics contend that sedation follows proportionality protocols for which LiPuma's thesis does not adequately account. Furthermore, sedation may not eliminate consciousness, and as such LiPuma's contention that CSD is equivalent to neocortical death is suspect. We not only defend the equivalence thesis, but also expand it to include additional moral considerations. First, we explain the equivalence thesis. This is followed by a defense of the thesis against five criticisms. The third section critiques the current use of CSD. Finally, we offer two proposals that, if adopted, would broaden the use of PAS/E and CSD and thereby expand options at the end-of-life.


Subject(s)
Deep Sedation , Euthanasia , Suicide, Assisted , Terminal Care , Humans , Terminal Care/methods , Palliative Care/methods , Death
2.
Blood Adv ; 7(7): 1146-1155, 2023 04 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36375132

ABSTRACT

The CORAL study highlighted the need to develop novel salvage regimens in relapsed/refractory (R/R) diffuse large B-cell lymphoma (DLBCL) previously treated with rituximab plus cyclophosphamide, doxorubicin, vincristine, and prednisone. Carfilzomib (CFZ) can overcome rituximab chemotherapy resistance in lymphoma preclinical models by targeting the ubiquitin-proteasome system. We conducted an investigator initiated, single-center, open-label, prospective phase 1 study evaluating the safety and efficacy of CFZ in combination with rituximab, ifosfamide, carboplatin, and etoposide (C-R-ICE) in high-dose chemotherapy with autologous stem cell transplant (HDC-ASCT) eligible patients with R/R DLBCL (NCT01959698). In the dose-escalation phase, 18 patients were enrolled at 6 dose levels with no dose-limiting toxicities noted. CFZ 45 mg/m2 was selected as the recommended dose for expansion. Eleven additional patients were enrolled in the dose-expansion phase. Overall response rate (ORR) was 66% (48% CR; 17% PR); 52% patients underwent HDC-ASCT. An ORR of 85% was observed in patients with nongerminal center B-cell-like (non-GCB) DLBCL compared with only 13% in those with GCB DLBCL. Median progression-free survival (PFS) was 15.2 months (5.1 months, not reached [NR]), and median overall survival (OS) was 22.6 months (6.8 months, NR). Patients with non-GCB subtype had a significantly longer PFS (NR vs 6.6 months; P = .0001) and OS (NR vs 6.6 months; P = .001) than those with GCB subtype. C-R-ICE is well tolerated in patients with R/R DLBCL with toxicities comparable to rituximab, ifosfamide, carboplatin, and etoposide therapy. Our data show that patients with non-GCB DLBCL benefit significantly from incorporating CFZ into second-line therapy and HDC-ASCT.


Subject(s)
Ifosfamide , Lymphoma, Large B-Cell, Diffuse , Humans , Rituximab , Ifosfamide/therapeutic use , Carboplatin/therapeutic use , Etoposide/adverse effects , Prospective Studies , Antibodies, Monoclonal, Murine-Derived , Lymphoma, Large B-Cell, Diffuse/pathology , Antineoplastic Combined Chemotherapy Protocols/adverse effects
3.
Am J Bioeth ; 22(7): 21-23, 2022 07.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35737490

Subject(s)
Algorithms , Morals , Humans
4.
Cancer ; 128(8): 1595-1604, 2022 04 15.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35157306

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Ofatumumab is a humanized type 1 anti-CD20 monoclonal antibody. Preclinical studies show improved complement-mediated cytotoxicity (CMC) compared to rituximab in mantle cell lymphoma (MCL). This study evaluates the safety and efficacy of combining ofatumumab with HyperCVAD/MA (O-HyperCVAD) in newly diagnosed MCL. METHODS: In this single-arm phase 2 study, 37 patients were treated with the combination of O-HyperCVAD for 4 or 6 cycles, followed by high dose chemotherapy and autologous stem cell transplant. Primary objectives were overall response rate (ORR) and complete response (CR) rate at the end of therapy. Secondary objectives included minimal residual disease (MRD) negativity, progression-free survival (PFS), and overall survival (OS). RESULTS: Median age was 60 years; ORR was 86% and 73% achieved a CR by modified Cheson criteria. The MRD negativity rate was 78% after 2 cycles of therapy, increasing to 96% at the end of induction; median PFS and OS were 45.5 months and 56 months, respectively. Achieving a post-induction CR by both imaging and flow cytometry was associated with improved PFS and OS. Early MRD negativity (post-2 cycles) was also associated with an improved PFS but not OS. There were 3 deaths while on therapy, and grades 3 and 4 adverse events (AEs) were observed in 22% and 68% of the patients. CONCLUSION: The addition of ofatumumab to HyperCVAD/HD-MA led to high rates of MRD negativity by flow cytometry in patients with newly diagnosed MCL. Achieving a CR post-induction by both imaging and flow cytometry is associated with improved overall survival.


Subject(s)
Antibodies, Monoclonal, Humanized , Lymphoma, Mantle-Cell , Adult , Antibodies, Monoclonal, Humanized/adverse effects , Antineoplastic Combined Chemotherapy Protocols/adverse effects , Humans , Lymphoma, Mantle-Cell/therapy , Middle Aged , Neoplasm, Residual/diagnosis , Rituximab
5.
Blood ; 138(9): 811-814, 2021 09 02.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34189565
10.
Health Serv Insights ; 9: 37-42, 2016.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27980420

ABSTRACT

The National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization (NHPCO) upholds policies prohibiting practices that deliberately hasten death. We find these policies overly restrictive and unreasonable. We argue that under specified circumstances it is both reasonable and morally sound to allow for treatments that may deliberately hasten death; these treatments should be part of the NHPCO guidelines. Broadening such policies would be more consistent with the gold standard of bioethical principles, ie, respecting the autonomy of competent adults.

11.
Camb Q Healthc Ethics ; 25(4): 674-85, 2016 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27634718

ABSTRACT

We argue that an advance directive (AD) is not invalidated by personality changes in dementia, as is claimed by Rebecca Dresser. The claim is that a new person results under such personality changes, and that the former person cannot write an AD for the new person. After stating the argument against ADs in cases of dementia, we provide a detailed examination of empirical studies of personality changes in dementia. This evidence, though not strong due mainly to low sample sizes and different notions of personal identity, does not support Dresser's position. Given the weakness in the empirical evidence, we turn to a philosophical defense of ADs based on a social contract view supporting the current interests of those writing ADs. Additionally, we argue that personality change is not equivalent to change in personal identity, as would be required by the argument against ADs in cases of dementia.


Subject(s)
Advance Directive Adherence , Advance Directives , Dementia/psychology , Individuality , Mental Competency , Personality , Decision Making , Ego , Humans
13.
J Clin Ethics ; 26(3): 266-9, 2015.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26399677

ABSTRACT

Susan D. McCammon and Nicole M. Piemonte offer a thoughtful and thorough commentary on our manuscript entitled "Expanding the use of Continuous Sedation Until Death." In this reply we attempt to clarify and further defend our position. We show how continuous sedation until death is not a "first resort" but rather a legitimate option among many that should available to terminally ill patients whose life expectancy is less than six months. We also attempt to show that we do not equivocate the meaning of palliative care as the commentators suggested. We argue that the traditional notion of palliative care should move beyond relief of "experienced suffering" to relief of potential suffering for those whose life expectancy is less than six months. Lastly, we challenge the commentator's position that the realm of ordinary medicine" should be the guide to care, by showing how the notion of ordinary medicine has been successfully challenged in both bioethical scholarship and the courts in a way that shows ordinary medicine to be an evolving concept rather than a static, universal guide.


Subject(s)
Decision Making/ethics , Deep Sedation/ethics , Pain Management/ethics , Palliative Care/ethics , Patient-Centered Care/ethics , Personal Autonomy , Terminal Care/ethics , Terminally Ill , Treatment Refusal , Humans , Male
14.
J Clin Ethics ; 26(2): 121-31, 2015.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26132059

ABSTRACT

As currently practiced, the use of continuous sedation until death (CSD) is controlled by clinicians in a way that may deny patients a key choice in controlling their dying process. Ethical guidelines from the American Medical Association and the American Academy of Pain Medicine describe CSD as a "last resort," and a position statement from the American Academy of Hospice and Palliative Medicine describe it as "an intervention reserved for extreme situations." Accordingly, patients must progress to unremitting pain and suffering and reach a last-resort stage before the option to pursue CSD is considered. Alternatively, we present and defend a new guideline in which decisionally capable, terminally ill patients who have a life expectancy of less than six months may request CSD before being subjected to the refractory suffering of a treatment of "last resort."


Subject(s)
Decision Making/ethics , Deep Sedation/ethics , Pain Management/ethics , Palliative Care/ethics , Patient-Centered Care/ethics , Personal Autonomy , Terminal Care/ethics , Terminally Ill , Treatment Refusal , Choice Behavior/ethics , Death , Euthanasia, Active, Voluntary/ethics , Euthanasia, Active, Voluntary/legislation & jurisprudence , Euthanasia, Active, Voluntary/trends , Health Personnel/ethics , Health Personnel/legislation & jurisprudence , Health Personnel/psychology , Hospice Care/ethics , Humans , Informed Consent/ethics , Informed Consent/standards , Life Expectancy , Lung Neoplasms/pathology , Male , Middle Aged , Moral Obligations , Netherlands , Pain/etiology , Pain Measurement , Palliative Care/methods , Palliative Care/trends , Patient-Centered Care/methods , Patient-Centered Care/trends , Practice Guidelines as Topic , Public Opinion , Social Values , Spinal Neoplasms/complications , Spinal Neoplasms/secondary , Stress, Psychological/prevention & control , Suicide, Assisted/ethics , Suicide, Assisted/legislation & jurisprudence , Suicide, Assisted/trends , Terminal Care/methods , Terminal Care/trends , Time Factors , Truth Disclosure/ethics , Uncertainty , United States , Withholding Treatment/ethics
16.
Am J Bioeth ; 14(4): 4-10, 2014.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24730479

ABSTRACT

Researchers designing a clinical trial may be aware of disputed evidence of serious risks from previous studies. These researchers must decide whether and how to describe these risks in their model informed consent document. They have an ethical obligation to provide fully informed consent, but does this obligation include notice of controversial evidence? With ACCORD as an example, we describe a framework and criteria that make clear the conditions requiring inclusion of important controversial risks. The ACCORD model consent document did not include notice of prior trials with excess death. We develop and explain a new standard labeled risk in equipoise. We argue that our approach provides an optimal level of integrity to protect the informational needs of the reasonable volunteers who agree to participate in clinical trials. We suggest language to be used in a model consent document and the informed consent discussion when such controversial evidence exists.


Subject(s)
Cause of Death , Clinical Trials as Topic/ethics , Informed Consent/ethics , Moral Obligations , Research Personnel/ethics , Therapeutic Equipoise , Truth Disclosure/ethics , Blood Glucose/metabolism , Cardiovascular Diseases/blood , Cardiovascular Diseases/prevention & control , Clinical Trials Data Monitoring Committees , Codes of Ethics , Decision Making , Drug Therapy, Combination , Ethics Committees, Research , Ethics, Research , Glycated Hemoglobin/metabolism , Humans , Hypoglycemic Agents/administration & dosage , Metformin/administration & dosage , Mortality/trends , Research Subjects , Risk , Sulfonylurea Compounds/administration & dosage , Uncertainty
18.
J Bioeth Inq ; 10(3): 383-92, 2013 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23784534

ABSTRACT

Recently both whole brain death (WBD) and higher brain death (HBD) have come under attack. These attacks, we argue, are successful, leaving supporters of both views without a firm foundation. This state of affairs has been described as "the death of brain death." Returning to a cardiopulmonary definition presents problems we also find unacceptable. Instead, we attempt to revive brain death by offering a novel and more coherent standard of death based on the permanent cessation of mental processing. This approach works, we claim, by being functionalist instead of being based in biology, consciousness, or personhood. We begin by explaining why an objective biological determination of death fails. We continue by similarly rejecting current arguments offered in support of HBD, which rely on consciousness and/or personhood. In the final section, we explain and defend our functionalist view of death. Our definition centers on mental processing, both conscious and preconscious or unconscious. This view provides the philosophical basis of a functional definition that most accurately reflects the original spirit of brain death when first proposed in the Harvard criteria of 1968.


Subject(s)
Brain Death , Brain , Consciousness , Ethics, Medical , Personhood , Unconsciousness , Death , Humans
19.
Diagn Microbiol Infect Dis ; 73(3): 243-5, 2012 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22571973

ABSTRACT

Lyme disease, the most commonly reported tick-borne infection in North America, is caused by infection with the spirochete Borrelia burgdorferi. Although an accurate clinical diagnosis can often be made based on the presence of erythema migrans, in research studies microbiologic or molecular microbiologic confirmation of the diagnosis may be required. In this study, we evaluated the sensitivity of 5 direct diagnostic methods (culture and nested polymerase chain reaction [PCR] of a 2-mm skin biopsy specimen, nested PCR and quantitative PCR (qPCR) performed on the same 1-mL aliquot of plasma and a novel qPCR-blood culture method) in 66 untreated adult patients with erythema migrans. Results of one or more of these tests were positive in 93.9% of the patients. Culture was more sensitive than PCR for both skin and blood, but the difference was only statistically significant for blood samples (P<0.005). Blood culture was significantly more likely to be positive in patients with multiple erythema migrans skin lesions compared to those with a single lesion (P=0.001). Positive test results among the 48 patients for whom all 5 assays were performed invariably included either a positive blood or a skin culture. The results of this study demonstrate that direct detection methods such as PCR and culture are highly sensitive in untreated adult patients with erythema migrans. This enabled microbiologic or molecular microbiologic confirmation of the diagnosis of B. burgdorferi infection in all but 4 (6.1%) of the 66 patients evaluated.


Subject(s)
Bacteriological Techniques/methods , Borrelia burgdorferi/isolation & purification , Lyme Disease/diagnosis , Molecular Diagnostic Techniques/methods , Adult , Aged , Aged, 80 and over , Borrelia burgdorferi/genetics , Borrelia burgdorferi/growth & development , Early Diagnosis , Female , Humans , Male , Middle Aged , Sensitivity and Specificity
20.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 20(3): 277-90, 2010 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21133336

ABSTRACT

Despite the attention that patient noncompliance has received from medical researchers, patient noncompliance remains poorly understood and difficult to alter. With a better theory of patient noncompliance, both greater success in achieving compliance and greater respect for patient decision making are likely. The theory presented, which uses a microeconomic approach, bridges a gap in the extant literature that has so far ignored the contributions of this classic perspective on decision making involving the tradeoff of costs and benefits. The model also generates a surprising conclusion: that patients are typically acting rationally when they refuse to comply with certain treatments. However, compliance is predicted to rise with increased benefits and reduced costs. The prediction that noncompliance is rational is especially true in chronic conditions at the point that treatment begins to move closer to the medically ideal treatment level. Although the details of this theory have not been tested empirically, it is well supported by existing prospective and retrospective studies.


Subject(s)
Choice Behavior , Patient Compliance , Treatment Refusal , Decision Making , Humans , Social Environment , Thinking
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...