Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 31
Filter
1.
Bioessays ; 46(6): e2300196, 2024 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38537114

ABSTRACT

This essay assesses the rationale for regulating research administrators as carefully as they regulate researchers. The reasons for such regulation are identical: protecting scientific integrity, ensuring responsible use of public funds, addressing the lack of effective recourse for victims, creating negative consequences for misbehaving actors, and addressing high incentives for misconduct. Whereas the reasons compelling us to regulate research administrators are obvious, counterarguments to administrative oversight are based on suggestions that the incidence and prevalence of cases of administrative misconduct are too low to warrant formal regulation. I briefly describe examples of the phenomenon drawn from publicly available records. My analysis suggests that the misconduct of research administrators is both serious and worthy of better oversight. Improved oversight of research administration will help steward tax dollars appropriately and enhance the overall integrity of the scientific record and of the free pursuit of knowledge more generally.


Subject(s)
Research Personnel , Humans , Scientific Misconduct , Administrative Personnel , Research
2.
Account Res ; 30(7): 439-458, 2023 12.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34989302

ABSTRACT

Virtually all of the scholarly literature on responsible conduct in research (RCR) focuses on the integrity of scientists - including why scientists misbehave, and how to improve training and enhance compliance with institutional and federal policies and regulations to prevent research misconduct. What this literature does not yet address is the integrity of those responsible for research administration. This article explores the responsible conduct of research administration and the potential for administrative misconduct. I highlight ways in which a lack of integrity in research administration can jeopardize the progress of science, the careers of researchers, and the reputation of institutions just as much as research misconduct can. Accordingly, I call for policies and appropriate oversight of research administration that are on par with policies governing research misconduct by scientists.


Subject(s)
Biomedical Research , Scientific Misconduct , Humans , Ethics, Research , Biomedical Research/education , Policy , Research Personnel/education
3.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 51(1): 47-51, 2021 Jan.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33630327

ABSTRACT

It now seems technically feasible to culture human embryos beyond the "fourteen-day limit," which has the potential to increase scientific understanding of human development and perhaps improve infertility treatments. The fourteen-day limit was adopted as a compromise but subsequently has been considered an ethical line. Does it remain relevant in light of technological advances permitting embryo maturation beyond it? Should it be changed and, if so, how and why? What justifications would be necessary to expand the limit, particularly given that doing so would violate some people's moral commitments regarding human embryos? Robust stakeholder engagement preceded adoption of the fourteen-day limit and should arguably be part of efforts to reassess it. Such engagement could also consider the need for enhanced oversight of human embryo research. In the meantime, developing and implementing reliable oversight systems should help foster high-quality research and public confidence in it.


Subject(s)
Embryo Research , Humans , Morals , Policy
4.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 48(6): 21-24, 2018 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30586185

ABSTRACT

As we reread Mary Shelley's Frankenstein at two hundred years, it is evident that Victor Frankenstein is both a mad scientist (fevered, obsessive) and a bad scientist (secretive, hubristic, irresponsible). He's also not a very nice person. He's a narcissist, a liar, and a bad "parent." But he is not genuinely evil. And yet when we reimagine him as evil-as an evil scientist and as an evil person-we can learn some important lessons about science and technology, our contemporary society, and ourselves.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/ethics , Cloning, Organism/psychology , Medicine in Literature , Parent-Child Relations , Disgust , Humans
10.
Sci Eng Ethics ; 15(3): 283-91, 2009 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19421896

ABSTRACT

It has been argued that bioethicists too often tend to represent the interests of scientists and not of the broader polity. Indeed, bioethicists seem predisposed to discard the voices and viewpoints of all but the cognoscenti. Focusing particularly on human pluripotent stem cell research, this commentary explores a variety of characterizations of bioethics and bioethicists in relation to forbidding science. Rather than proselytizing or prohibiting, bioethicists should work in partnership with scientists and publics to craft scientifically well-informed and morally sophisticated debates about forbidding science.


Subject(s)
Bioethics , Biomedical Research/ethics , Ethicists , Ethics, Research , Biomedical Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryo Research/ethics , Ethicists/legislation & jurisprudence , Humans , Moral Obligations , Pluripotent Stem Cells , Professional Role
11.
Am J Public Health ; 99(2): 210-5, 2009 Feb.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19059852

ABSTRACT

An apparent consensus governs the management of carrier status information generated incidentally through newborn screening: results cannot be withheld from parents. This normative stance encodes the focus on autonomy and distaste for paternalism that characterize the principles of clinical bioethics. However, newborn screening is a classic public health intervention in which paternalism may trump autonomy and through which parents are-in effect-required to receive carrier information. In truth, the disposition of carrier results generates competing moral infringements: to withhold information or require its possession. Resolving this dilemma demands consideration of a distinctive body of public health ethics to highlight the moral imperatives associated with the exercise of collective authority in the pursuit of public health benefits.


Subject(s)
Consensus , Disclosure/ethics , Genetic Testing , Neonatal Screening , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Public Health/ethics
12.
Am J Bioeth ; 8(3): 43-51, 2008 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-18570103

ABSTRACT

Calls for the "translation" of research from bench to bedside are increasingly demanding. What is translation, and why does it matter? We sketch the recent history of outcome-oriented translational research in the United States, with a particular focus on the Roadmap Initiative of the National Institutes of Health (Bethesda, MD). Our main example of contemporary translational research is stem cell research, which has superseded genomics as the translational object of choice. We explore the nature of and obstacles to translational research and assess the ethical and biomedical challenges of embracing a translational ethos.


Subject(s)
Biomedical Research/economics , Biomedical Research/ethics , Ethics, Research , Financing, Government , Research Support as Topic , Stem Cells , Biomedical Research/history , Biomedical Research/standards , Biomedical Research/trends , Diffusion of Innovation , Embryo Research/economics , Embryo Research/ethics , Financing, Government/history , Financing, Government/legislation & jurisprudence , Financing, Government/standards , Foundations , History, 20th Century , History, 21st Century , Human Genome Project , Humans , National Institutes of Health (U.S.) , Research Support as Topic/history , Research Support as Topic/legislation & jurisprudence , Research Support as Topic/standards , United States
15.
Am J Bioeth ; 7(4): 80-2; discussion W7-9, 2007 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17455008
17.
Account Res ; 13(3): 207-24, 2006.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17124758

ABSTRACT

The US National Academy of Sciences (NAS) recently published voluntary guidelines for human embryonic stem (hES) cell research. The NAS guidelines propose two levels of oversight. AT the local level, research institutions are to create Embryonic Stem Cell Research Oversight (ESCRO) committees with a mandate to assess the scientific merit and ethical acceptability of hES cell research. At the national level, a new committee is to be created, not to review specific research proposals, but rather to periodically assess, and as needed revise, the NAS guidelines. In this article, we critically assess this proposal. In particular, we review the benefits and limitations of local research review. On this basis, we argue that local review is insufficient for hES cell research and that while there are obvious pragmatic and political reasons for the NAS to favor local research review, there are more compelling reasons for the NAS to have recommended national review of hES cell research proposals.


Subject(s)
Embryo Research/ethics , Embryonic Stem Cells , Ethical Review/standards , Ethics Committees, Research/organization & administration , Guidelines as Topic , National Academy of Sciences, U.S. , Advisory Committees/organization & administration , Conflict of Interest , Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryonic Stem Cells/cytology , Federal Government , Government Regulation , Humans , Research Support as Topic , United States
19.
Am J Bioeth ; 6(4): W29-41, 2006.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16885087

ABSTRACT

As compared with conventional vaccine production systems, plant-made vaccines (PMVs) are said to enjoy a range of advantages including cost of production and ease of storage for distribution in developing countries. In this article, we introduce the science of PMV production, and address ethical issues associated with development and clinical testing of PMVs within three interrelated domains: PMVs as transgenic plants; PMVs as clinical research materials; and PMVs as agents of global health. We present three conclusions: first, while many of the ethical issues raised by PMVs are familiar, PMVs add a new dimension to old issues, and raise some novel issues for ethicists and policy-makers; secondly, it is premature to promise broad applicability of PMVs across the developing world without having demonstrated their feasibility; thirdly, in particular, proponents of PMVs as a solution to global health problems must, as a condition of the ethical conduct of their research, define the commercial feasibility of PMVs for distribution in the developing world.


Subject(s)
Bioethical Issues , Biotechnology/ethics , Genetic Engineering/ethics , Global Health , Plants, Genetically Modified , Vaccines/biosynthesis , Genetic Engineering/methods , Humans , Plants, Genetically Modified/metabolism
20.
FASEB J ; 20(7): 838-45, 2006 May.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16675841

ABSTRACT

The National Academy of Sciences recently issued voluntary guidelines to govern human embryonic stem cell research. Among other restrictions, these guidelines prohibit certain kinds of combinations of human and nonhuman animal cells, and call for ethics review and oversight of any protocol involving the transfer of human embryonic stem cells into nonhuman animals. In this essay, I discuss the history of and scientific rationales for combining human cells with cells of nonhuman animals, and critically assess the most recent attempts to limit such research on moral grounds--and find them lacking. Nonetheless, as I show, this research remains scientifically and morally contested. I then explore whether and how the NAS's recommended Embryonic Stem Cell Research and Oversight committees will allow for scientifically well-informed moral assessment of this controversial, but possibly important, research.


Subject(s)
Chimera/growth & development , Embryo Research/ethics , Stem Cells/cytology , Animals , Bioethical Issues/standards , Guidelines as Topic , Humans , Mice , Public Policy , United States
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...