Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 24
Filter
3.
J Med Ethics ; 49(10): 661-662, 2023 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37739438
9.
Nurs Ethics ; 28(7-8): 1294-1305, 2021.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33719736

ABSTRACT

The American College of Nurse-Midwives, American Society for Pain Management Nursing, American Academy of Pediatrics, and other largely US-based medical organizations have argued that at least some forms of non-therapeutic child genital cutting, including routine penile circumcision, are ethically permissible even when performed on non-consenting minors. In support of this view, these organizations have at times appealed to potential health benefits that may follow from removing sexually sensitive, non-diseased tissue from the genitals of such minors. We argue that these appeals to "health benefits" as a way of justifying medically unnecessary child genital cutting practices may have unintended consequences. For example, it may create a "loophole" through which certain forms of female genital cutting-or female genital "mutilation" as it is defined by the World Health Organization-could potentially be legitimized. Moreover, by comparing current dominant Western attitudes toward female genital "mutilation" and so-called intersex genital "normalization" surgeries (i.e. surgeries on children with certain differences of sex development), we show that the concept of health invoked in each case is inconsistent and culturally biased. It is time for Western healthcare organizations-including the American College of Nurse-Midwives, American Society for Pain Management Nursing, American Academy of Pediatrics, and World Health Organization-to adopt a more consistent concept of health and a unified ethical stance when it comes to child genital cutting practices.


Subject(s)
Circumcision, Female , Circumcision, Male , Child , Circumcision, Female/adverse effects , Female , Genitalia , Humans , Male , Morals , United States
11.
Glob Public Health ; 16(12): 1804-1819, 2021 12.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33151788

ABSTRACT

The Global Gag Rule is a United States policy that blocks global health funding to foreign non-governmental organisations if they engage in abortion-related activities. It has been implemented by every Republican administration since 1984 and remains in operation at the time of writing in its most stringent and extensive form. It has been criticised for its implications for women's bodily autonomy, its censorship of non-governmental organisations and health professionals, and for its impact on the health of populations in affected countries. To capture the effects of the policy to date, we conducted a scoping review in April 2020. Forty-eight articles met our eligibility criteria, and were analysed thematically, noting the effects on: the operations of non-governmental organisations; maternal health; sexually transmitted infections; marginalised groups; reproductive rights. We found that the policy increased the abortion rate and had a negative impact on maternal health, STIs, and the health of marginalised groups. We conclude that the policy amounts to the neocolonial co-optation of sexual and reproductive health in the Global South to advance an ideological agenda in the Global North. We urge that the policy be repealed as part of the broader project of protecting and decolonising sexual and reproductive health globally.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Global Health , Female , Humans , Internationality , Pregnancy , Reproductive Health , Reproductive Rights , United States , Women's Rights
12.
Dev World Bioeth ; 21(4): 211-226, 2021 12.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32909369

ABSTRACT

Campaigns to circumcise millions of boys and men to reduce HIV transmission are being conducted throughout eastern and southern Africa, recommended by the World Health Organization and implemented by the United States government and Western NGOs. In the United States, proposals to mass-circumcise African and African American men are longstanding, and have historically relied on racist beliefs and stereotypes. The present campaigns were started in haste, without adequate contextual research, and the manner in which they have been carried out implies troubling assumptions about culture, health, and sexuality in Africa, as well as a failure to properly consider the economic determinants of HIV prevalence. This critical appraisal examines the history and politics of these circumcision campaigns while highlighting the relevance of race and colonialism. It argues that the "circumcision solution" to African HIV epidemics has more to do with cultural imperialism than with sound health policy, and concludes that African communities need a means of robust representation within the regime.


Subject(s)
Circumcision, Male , HIV Infections , Africa , HIV Infections/prevention & control , Health Policy , Human Experimentation , Humans , Male , United States
13.
Front Med (Lausanne) ; 7: 570551, 2020.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33163500
14.
J Med Ethics ; 2020 Aug 24.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32839230

ABSTRACT

Many healthcare goods, such as surgical instruments, textiles and gloves, are manufactured in unregulated factories and sweatshops where, amongst other labour rights violations, workers are subject to considerable occupational health risks. In this paper we undertake an ethical analysis of the supply of sweatshop-produced surgical goods to healthcare providers, with a specific focus on the National Health Service of the United Kingdom. We contend that while labour abuses and occupational health deficiencies are morally unacceptable in the production of any commodity, an additional wrong is incurred when the health of certain populations is secured in ways that endanger the health and well-being of people working and living elsewhere. While some measures have been taken to better regulate the supply chain to healthcare providers in the UK, further action is needed to ensure that surgical goods are sourced from suppliers who protect the labour and occupational health rights of their workers.

15.
J Med Ethics ; 46(5): 328-336, 2020 05.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32220866

ABSTRACT

In this paper, I argue that men should take primary responsibility for protecting against pregnancy. Male long-acting reversible contraceptives are currently in development, and, once approved, should be used as the standard method for avoiding pregnancy. Since women assume the risk of pregnancy when they engage in penis-in-vagina sex, men should do their utmost to ensure that their ejaculations are responsible, otherwise women shoulder a double burden of pregnancy risk plus contraceptive responsibility. Changing the expectations regarding responsibility for contraception would render penis-in-vagina sex more equitable, and could lead to a shift in the discourse around abortion access. I describe the sex asymmetries of contraceptive responsibility and of pregnancy-related risk, and offer arguments in favour of men taking primary responsibility for contraception. My arguments centre on: (1) analogies between contraception and vaccination, and unwanted pregnancy and disease; (2) a veil-of-ignorance approach, in which I contend that if a person were not told their sex, they would find a society in which men were expected to acquire and use effective contraceptives the fairest arrangement for everyone.


Subject(s)
Contraceptive Agents, Male , Ejaculation , Contraception , Contraception Behavior , Female , Humans , Male , Morals , Pregnancy
16.
Health Care Anal ; 27(3): 202-219, 2019 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31161409

ABSTRACT

During the "age of austerity" the UK government has progressively limited free health services for "overseas visitors" on the grounds of fairness and frugality. This is despite the fact that the cost of the additional bureaucracy required by the new system and the public health consequences are expected to exceed the sums saved. In this article I explore the interaction between the discourses of austerity and xenophobia as they relate to migrants' access to healthcare. By examining the available data and adjudicating various moral arguments, I cast doubt on the claim that the current charging regulations are cost-effective and fair. I instead contend that if the UK is concerned with running a health service that is economically-sustainable and morally-defensible, it is critical that migrants are welcomed, both as staff and as patients. I conclude by arguing that xenophobia has precipitated changes to the health service which do not qualify as "austerity" in the way that is claimed, but rather deliberately produce a "hostile environment" for migrants, despite this very likely generating economic losses.


Subject(s)
Health Services/supply & distribution , State Medicine , Transients and Migrants , Xenophobia , Health Services/economics , Health Services Accessibility/economics , Health Services Accessibility/ethics , Humans , Public Health , Racism , United Kingdom
17.
J Med Ethics ; 45(8): 489-496, 2019 08.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31023767

ABSTRACT

Pregnancy care is chargeable for migrants who do not have indefinite leave to remain in the UK. Women who are not 'ordinarily resident', including prospective asylum applicants, some refused asylum-seekers, unidentified victims of trafficking and undocumented people are required to pay substantial charges in order to access antenatal, intrapartum and postnatal services as well as abortion care within the National Health Service. In this paper, we consider the ethical issues generated by the exclusion of pregnancy care from the raft of services which are free to all. We argue that charging for pregnancy care amounts to sex discrimination, since without pregnancy care, sex may pose a barrier to good health. We also argue that charging for pregnancy care violates bodily autonomy, entrenches the sex asymmetry of sexual responsibility, centres the male body and produces health risks for women and neonates. We explore some of the ideological motivations for making maternity care chargeable, and suggest that its exclusion responds to xenophobic populism. We recommend that pregnancy care always be free regardless of citizenship or residence status, and briefly explore how these arguments bear on the broader moral case against chargeable healthcare for migrants.


Subject(s)
Health Services Accessibility/economics , Maternal Health Services , State Medicine , Transients and Migrants , Contraception , Eligibility Determination , Female , Health Services Accessibility/statistics & numerical data , Humans , Maternal Health Services/economics , Maternal Health Services/statistics & numerical data , Moral Obligations , Patient Credit and Collection , Pregnancy , Prospective Studies , United Kingdom/epidemiology , Xenophobia
18.
Dev World Bioeth ; 19(4): 224-234, 2019 12.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30891895

ABSTRACT

Neglected tropical diseases are defined operationally as diseases that prevail in "tropical" regions and are under-researched, under-funded, and under-treated compared with their disease burden. By analysing the adjectives "tropical" and "neglected," I expose and interrogate the discourses within which the term "neglected tropical disease" derives its meaning. First, I argue that the term "tropical" conjures the notion of "tropicality," a form of Othering which erroneously explains the disease-prevalence of "tropical" regions by reference to environmental determinism, rather than colonialism and neocolonialism. Second, I examine the way in which this Othering enables the abjection of tropical regions and their peoples, leading to neglect. I recommend that the term "neglected tropical diseases" be more carefully contextualised within health scholarship, education, and policy.


Subject(s)
Neglected Diseases/classification , Terminology as Topic , Tropical Medicine/classification , Communicable Disease Control , Humans , World Health Organization
19.
J Bioeth Inq ; 16(1): 99-112, 2019 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30570716

ABSTRACT

Women are over-represented within alternative medicine, both as consumers and as service providers. In this paper, I show that the appeal of alternative medicine to women relates to the neglect of women's health needs within scientific medicine. This is concerning because alternative medicine is severely limited in its therapeutic effects; therefore, those who choose alternative therapies are liable to experience inadequate healthcare. I argue that while many patients seek greater autonomy in alternative medicine, the absence of an evidence base and plausible mechanisms of action leaves patients unable to realize meaningful autonomy. This seems morally troubling, especially given that the neglect of women's needs within scientific medicine seems to contribute to preferences for alternative medicine. I conclude that the liberatory credentials of alternative medicine should be questioned and make recommendations to render scientific medicine better able to meet the needs of typical alternative medicine consumers.


Subject(s)
Complementary Therapies , Women's Health , Female , Feminism , Humans , Personal Autonomy
20.
Health Hum Rights ; 20(1): 53-65, 2018 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30008552

ABSTRACT

Podoconiosis is a debilitating chronic swelling of the foot and lower leg caused by long-term exposure to irritant red volcanic clay soil in the highland regions of Africa, Central America, and India. In this paper, we consider the human rights violations that cause, and are caused by, podoconiosis in Ethiopia. Specifically, we discuss the way in which the right to an adequate basic standard of living is not met in endemic regions, where the following basic necessities are not readily available: appropriate footwear, health education, and affordable, accessible health care. Those living with podoconiosis experience disablement, stigma and discrimination, and mental distress, contributing to greater impoverishment and a reduced quality of life. We suggest that while identifying rights violations is key to characterizing the scale and nature of the problem, identifying duties is critical to eliminating podoconiosis. To this end, we describe the duties of the Ethiopian government, the international community, and those sourcing Ethiopian agricultural products in relation to promoting shoe-wearing, providing adequate health care, and improving health literacy.


Subject(s)
Elephantiasis/prevention & control , Elephantiasis/therapy , Human Rights , Shoes , Elephantiasis/epidemiology , Ethiopia/epidemiology , Female , Health Services Accessibility/organization & administration , Humans , Male , Poverty , Quality of Life/psychology , Social Stigma , Soil/chemistry
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...