Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 30
Filter
Add more filters










Publication year range
1.
HEC Forum ; 2024 May 14.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38743177

ABSTRACT

Jeremy Williams argues that both anti-abortion and pro-choice theories seem to justify two forms of anti-abortion violence - (1) violence against those that perform abortions, and (2) the subjugation of women seeking abortion. He illustrates this by way of his Death Camps analogy. However, Williams does not advocate such violence; rather he seems despondent over his conclusion. Here I argue Williams' conclusion turns on confusion regarding the restrictivist position and a failure to adequately meet the challenge of Thomson's Violinist case. The Death Camps analogy is incomparable to the practice of abortion because it fails to capture the risks, burdens, and rights relationships present in pregnancy.

2.
Bioethics ; 38(5): 419-424, 2024 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38652592

ABSTRACT

Parthenogenesis is a form of asexual reproduction in which a gamete (ovum or sperm) develops without being fertilized. Tomer Jordi Chaffer uses parthenogenesis to challenge Don Marquis' future-like-ours (FLO) argument against abortion. According to Marquis, (1) what makes it morally wrong to kill us is that it would deprive us of a possible future that we might come to value-a future "like ours" (FLO) and (2) human fetuses are numerically identical to any adult human organism they may develop into, and thus have a FLO. Chaffer contends that if human ova are capable of parthenogenesis, then they would have a FLO, which contraception may deprive them of, but contends this is absurd. Bruce P. Blackshaw challenges Chaffer, contending sexually fertilized embryos are not identical to unfertilized ovum, but this would yield a more absurd implication, that fertilization deprives an ovum of a FLO! Here I show Marquis' account of identity rules out both Chaffer's and Blackshaw's accounts.


Subject(s)
Parthenogenesis , Humans , Female , Pregnancy , Male , Abortion, Induced/ethics , Value of Life , Fertilization , Ovum , Fetus
3.
Camb Q Healthc Ethics ; 33(2): 296-299, 2024 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38444239

ABSTRACT

Emily Carroll and Parker Crutchfield propose a new inconsistency argument against abortion restrictivism. In response, I raised several objections to their argument. Recently Carroll and Crutchfield have replied and seem to be under the impression that I'm a restrictivist. This is puzzling, since my criticism of their view included a very thinly veiled, but purposely more charitable, anti-restrictivist inconsistency argument. In this response, I explain how Carroll and Crutchfield mischaracterize my position and that of the restrictivist.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Pregnancy , Female , Humans , Dissent and Disputes
4.
J Med Ethics ; 2023 Sep 21.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37734907

ABSTRACT

Hendricks set out to construct an antiabortion version of Jeff McMahan's Embryo Rescue case in which you have two choices-(1) save a woman from an unwilling pregnancy or (2) save a fetus from being killed. In his Pregnancy Rescue case, he contends we ought to choose (2), which he thinks shows abortion is immoral. However, I argue the Pregnancy Rescue case is a false dilemma because you can save both. I propose an alternative, more elegant dilemma, the Ectogenesis Rescue case with the same choices (1) and (2). Hendricks also believes his case can serve as an antiabortion version of Thomson's Violinist case, showing that abortion is immoral even if a fetus is not a person. However, while Thomson's Violinist substitutes the fetus with a person, Hendricks fails to substitute the fetus with something that is not a person. I propose an alternative, the Snakebite Rescue case, which does this.

5.
J Med Ethics ; 2023 Aug 08.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37553223

ABSTRACT

Räsänen draws a distinction between chronological age and biological age and argues that biological ageing is (sometimes) desirable. To demonstrate this, he asks us to consider the case of April, who like Karel Capek's Elina Makropulos, has stopped biologically ageing. Unlike Makropulos, though, April's biological ageing was halted before puberty, so she will never mature into adulthood. Räsänen contends this case shows ageing can be desirable, but this equivocates between maturing and ageing. Here I argue biological ageing, or the wear and tear normally associated with chronological ageing, is prima facie undesirable, but that maturing can be prima facie desirable.

6.
Asian Bioeth Rev ; 15(2): 169-179, 2023 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37035483

ABSTRACT

In his recent article "Even if the fetus is not a person, abortion is immoral: The Impairment Argument," Perry Hendricks sets out to sidestep thorny metaphysical questions regarding human fetuses and present a new argument against abortion - if impairing a fetus with fetal alcohol syndrome is immoral, then killing the fetus is immoral. Hendricks takes inspiration from Judith Jarvis Thomson's defense of abortion - that even if fetuses are persons with a right to life, the right to life is not the right to use others, so it is acceptable to induce abortion. Together with Bruce Blackshaw, Hendricks set out to strengthen the impairment argument by appealing to Don Marquis's future like ours (FLO) account of the wrongness of killing. Here I argue the impairment argument falls short in three ways. First, Hendricks and Blackshaw fail to assume fetuses aren't persons, broadly construed. Second, they fail to show that impairing a fetus is immoral. Third, they overlook abortions that (merely) let the fetus die. Finally, I argue Thomson's defense of abortion preempts the significance of the impairment argument; Thomson seems to show that even if killing a fetus is prima facie immoral, women still have the right to induce abortion.

7.
J Med Ethics ; 49(11): 781-782, 2023 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36693700

ABSTRACT

Colgrove challenges Doug Hardman's account of deception in medicine. Hardman contends physicians can unintentionally deceive their patients, illustrating this by way of an acupuncturist who believes what she says despite insufficient medical evidence, falling short of what Hardman believes adequate disclosure requires. Colgrove argues deception requires intent but constructs an alternative case in which an acupuncturist does not believe what he tells the patient, but purportedly lacks an intent to deceive. Here, I argue that both acupuncturists deceive, and both can be said to do so intentionally. Neither lies, but rather they seem to engage another deceptive form of speech, what Frankfurt calls bullshit. Building on Colgrove's case, I argue cases where a physician's disclosure includes reading a script they do not believe, this is both deceptive and contrary to professional medical ethics.

8.
New Bioeth ; 28(4): 315-326, 2022 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36121890

ABSTRACT

Many people believe the morality of abortion stands or falls on the moral status of the fetus, with abortion opponents arguing fetuses are persons with a right to life. Judith Jarvis Thomson bypasses this debate, arguing that even if we assume fetuses have a right to life, this is not a right to use other people's bodies. Recently Perry Hendricks attempts to bypass discussion of rights, assuming that if he can show that some people have a right to use other's bodies, then we ought to restrict abortion (and perhaps compel organ donation, charity, etc.). Hendricks attempts to illustrate this by way of a Feinberg-style cabin case. I argue Hendricks' restrictivist argument fails.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Abortion, Spontaneous , Pregnancy , Female , Male , Humans , Value of Life , Dissent and Disputes , Fetus , Personhood
10.
J Med Ethics ; 48(7): 461-465, 2022 07.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34016648

ABSTRACT

Most opposition to induced abortion turns on the belief that human fetuses are persons from conception. On this view, the moral status of the fetus alone requires those in a position to provide aid-gestational mothers-to make tremendous sacrifices to benefit the fetus. Recently, critics have argued that this pro-life position requires more than opposition to induced abortion. Pro-life theorists are relatively silent on the issues of spontaneous abortion, surplus in vitro fertilisation human embryos, and the suffering and death of born persons due to lack of access to food, shelter and medical care. Colgrove et al call such arguments inconsistency arguments, arguing they 'do not matter' and mischaracterise them as ad hominem attacks. Here, I argue these are better understood as moral dilemmas. While some critics argue pro-life inaction is evidence that they do not really believe human fetuses are persons, I contend this inaction is likely the result of resolvable confusion rather than moral negligence.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Abortion, Spontaneous , Dissent and Disputes , Female , Fetus , Humans , Moral Obligations , Morals , Personhood , Pregnancy , Value of Life
11.
Asian Bioeth Rev ; 14(1): 41-56, 2022 Jan.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34729080

ABSTRACT

Most opponents of abortion (OA) believe fetuses matter. Critics argue that OA act inconsistently with regards to fetal life, seeking to restrict access to induced abortion, but largely ignoring spontaneous abortion and the creation of surplus embryos by IVF. Nicholas Colgrove, Bruce Blackshaw, and Daniel Rodger call such arguments inconsistency arguments and contend they do not matter. They present three objections to these arguments - the other beliefs, other actions, and hypocrisy objection. Previously, I argued these objections fail and threaten to undermine ethical inquiry. Colgrove et al. have recently replied, but here, I argue their reply fails as well and raises a new criticism of the other actions' objection. This essay sets out to show, as well as any philosophical argument can, that inconsistency arguments are morally significant.

12.
Bioethics ; 35(9): 910-915, 2021 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34416042

ABSTRACT

Bruce P. Blackshaw and Daniel Rodger contend that if we assume fetuses are persons, then abortion is a public health crisis that justifies overriding a gestational mother's rights and compelling her to carry the fetus to term, but dawdle addressing greater public health crises like spontaneous abortion and hunger. They draw a distinction between deliberate and indeliberate harm to justify restricting rights in the former, but not the latter; but such distinction fails to justify restricting rights in most public health crises. Furthermore, it fails to justify curtailing abortion rights as unwilling gestational mothers might deliberately induce abortion in self-defense, merely indeliberately harming the fetus.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Abortion, Spontaneous , Female , Fetus , Humans , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Pregnancy , Public Health
13.
Asian Bioeth Rev ; 13(3): 317-334, 2021 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34295386

ABSTRACT

Mitochondrial replacement techniques (MRTs) are designed to allow couples to have children without passing on mitochondrial diseases. Recently, Giulia Cavaliere and César Palacios-González argued that prospective parents have the right to use MRTs to pursue genetic relatedness, such that some same-sex couples and/or polygamous triads could use the process to impart genetic relatedness between a child and more of its caregivers. Although MRTs carry medical risks, Cavaliere and Palacios-González contend that because MRTs are identity-affecting, they do not cause harm to an existing human being, and our intuitions otherwise arise from the non-identity problem. Here, I review several attempts to address the non-identity problem, and propose a solution to the problem. Furthermore, I argue that regardless of one's stance on whether MRTs are identity-affecting, the use of MRTs to pursue genetic relatedness alone falls outside the scope of the medical profession, as they involve substantive medical risk for no medical benefit.

14.
Bioethics ; 35(7): 680-687, 2021 09.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34128235

ABSTRACT

In a recent article Thomas Douglas and Katrien Devolder propose a theory of genetic parenthood according to which a human child can have only two genetic human parents. I argue this theory is arbitrarily narrow and fails to account for cases such as hybrids, cloning, chimerism, twinning, parthenogenesis, mitochondrial replacement techniques, and more. I propose an alternate theory of genetic parenthood, one that is prima facie consistent with our commonsense intuitions about genetic parenthood and relevant to a right to procreative autonomy.


Subject(s)
Parents , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted , Child , Cloning, Organism , Humans , Reproduction
15.
Bioethics ; 35(5): 400-406, 2021 06.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33527428

ABSTRACT

Most opposition to abortion stands or falls on whether a fetus is the sort of being whose life it is seriously wrong to end. In her influential paper 'A defense of abortion,' Judith Jarvis Thomson effectively sidesteps this issue, assuming the fetus is a person with the right to life yet arguing this alone does not give it the right to use the mother's body. In a recent article, Perry Hendricks takes inspiration from Thomson and assumes the fetus is not a person, arguing that abortion is wrong because causing fetal impairment is wrong and abortion is worse than causing fetal impairment. Here I argue Hendricks' impairment argument fails. For Hendricks, risking fetal impairment is wrong because it risks harm to a future person, but if we assume the fetus is not a person, abortion doesn't harm anyone, it merely prevents them from existing.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Abortion, Spontaneous , Dissent and Disputes , Female , Fetus , Humans , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Pregnancy , Value of Life
16.
J Med Ethics ; 46(9): 617-622, 2020 09.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32220867

ABSTRACT

To avoid potential abuse and respect patient autonomy, physicians have a moral obligation to obtain informed consent before performing any significant medical intervention. To give informed consent, a patient must be competent, understand her condition, options and their expected risks and benefits and must freely and expressly consent to one of those options. Shlomo Cohen challenges this conception of informed consent by constructing cases based on Edmund Gettier's classic counterexamples to traditional theories of knowledge. In this paper, I argue Cohen-style cases are not genuine threats to the concept of informed consent, however they provide an interesting challenge to theories of conscientious objection.


Subject(s)
Informed Consent , Physicians , Female , Humans , Moral Obligations , Personal Autonomy
17.
J Med Ethics ; 46(2): 93-98, 2020 02.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31537616

ABSTRACT

The contemporary philosophical literature on abortion primarily revolves around three seemingly intractable debates, concerning the (1) moral status of the fetus, (2) scope of women's rights and (3) moral relevance of the killing/letting die distinction. The possibility of ectogenesis-technology that would allow a fetus to develop outside of a gestational mother's womb-presents a unique opportunity for moral compromise. Here, I argue those opposed to abortion have a prima facie moral obligation to pursue ectogenesis technology and provide ectogenesis for disconnected fetuses as part of a moral compromise.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Dissent and Disputes , Ectogenesis/ethics , Personhood , Reproductive Techniques/ethics , Women's Rights , Abortion, Legal , Cooperative Behavior , Ethics , Female , Fetal Development , Fetus , Humans , Moral Obligations , Pregnancy , Reproduction/ethics , Social Values , Uterus
18.
Bioethics ; 33(9): 1002-1011, 2019 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31318435

ABSTRACT

Most serious contemporary opposition to abortion is grounded on the belief that human fetuses are members of the same moral category as beings like us, and that the loss of any such life is one of the worst possible losses. Substance view theorists oppose abortion for this reason: in their view beings like us are essentially rational substances with inherent moral worth, and those who perform induced abortion fail to recognize this moral worth. In a recent series of articles, Rob Lovering presents reductio-style arguments against the substance view, in part arguing that it is inconsistent with our intuitions in rescue and spontaneous abortion cases. In a recent reply, Henrik Friberg-Fernros argues that the substance view can evade these problematic implications because of a distinction between killing and letting die. According to this argument, the fetus's right to life is a negative right not to be killed, not a positive right to be rescued, thus the anti-abortion theorist who lets fetuses die acts acceptably. I argue this stance fails to recognize the inherent moral worth that the substance view contends fetuses possess. One who refrains from saving a person, or doesn't care how many people she saves, cannot reasonably claim to value life. Furthermore, this stance is at odds with most contemporary anti-abortion views that oppose induced abortions of both the killing and letting die variety.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Fetal Development , Human Rights/ethics , Morals , Value of Life , Adult , Female , Humans , Pregnancy
19.
J Med Ethics ; 45(7): 469-470, 2019 07.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31302604

ABSTRACT

Joona Räsänen argues some people have a right to change their legal age to prevent age discrimination. He proposes two prerequisites-the person feels his age differs from his legal age, and that person's biological age differs from his chronological age. I argue we can achieve the same protections from ageism through restricting access to one's birth date. I review several moral reasons in favour of changing one's legal age, concluding the enterprise is folly.


Subject(s)
Morals , Humans , Male
20.
J Med Ethics ; 45(8): 562-564, 2019 08.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31221765

ABSTRACT

Most opposition to abortion turns on the claim that human fetuses are full moral agents from conception (or soon afterwards). Critics argue that antiabortion theorists act hypocritically when they neglect spontaneous abortions-valuing some fetal lives and not others. Many philosophers draw a distinction between killing and letting die, with the former being morally impermissible and latter acceptable. Henrick Friberg-Fernros appeals to this distinction with his Two Tragedies Argument, contending that anti-abortion theorists are justified in prioritising preventing induced abortions over spontaneous ones, as the former involves two tragedies-a death and a killing. However, induced abortion can involve either killing or letting die, and thus this view is incompatible with the traditional anti-abortion view. Furthermore, Friberg-Fernros appears to value preventing killing attempts more than preventing actual deaths.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Death , Dissent and Disputes , Female , Fetus , Humans , Morals , Pregnancy
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...