Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 5 de 5
Filter
1.
BMC Med Ethics ; 19(1): 64, 2018 06 22.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29929500

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Health checks or health screenings identify (risk factors for) disease in people without a specific medical indication. So far, the perspective of (potential) health check users has remained underexposed in discussions about the ethics and regulation of health checks. METHODS: In 2017, we conducted a qualitative study with lay people from the Netherlands (four focus groups). We asked what participants consider characteristics of good and bad health checks, and whether they saw a role for the Dutch government. RESULTS: Participants consider a good predictive value the most important characteristic of a good health check. Information before, during and after the test, knowledgeable and reliable providers, tests for treatable (risk factors for) disease, respect for privacy, no unnecessary health risks and accessibility are also mentioned as criteria for good health checks. Participants make many assumptions about health check offers. They assume health checks provide certainty about the presence or absence of disease, that health checks offer opportunities for health benefits and that the privacy of health check data is guaranteed. In their choice for provider and test they tend to rely more on heuristics than information. Participants trust physicians to put the interest of potential health check users first and expect the Dutch government to intervene if providers other than physicians failed to do so by offering tests with a low predictive value, or tests that may harm people, or by infringing the privacy of users. CONCLUSIONS: Assumptions of participants are not always justified, but they may influence the choice to participate. This is problematic because choices for checks with a low predictive value that do not provide health benefits may create uncertainty and may cause harm to health; an outcome diametrically opposite to the one intended. Also, this may impair the relationship of trust with physicians and the Dutch government. To further and protect autonomous choice and to maintain trust, we recommend the following measures to timely adjust false expectations: advertisements that give an accurate impression of health check offers, and the installation of a quality mark.


Subject(s)
Mass Screening , Attitude to Health , Confidentiality , Female , Focus Groups , Government Regulation , Health Status , Heuristics , Humans , Male , Mass Screening/ethics , Mass Screening/legislation & jurisprudence , Mass Screening/psychology , Netherlands , Physician-Patient Relations , Trust , Unnecessary Procedures/ethics , Unnecessary Procedures/psychology
2.
BMC Med Ethics ; 18(1): 55, 2017 Oct 02.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28969671

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Health checks identify (risk factors for) disease in people without symptoms. They may be offered by the government through population screenings and by other providers to individual users as 'personal health checks'. Health check providers' perspective of 'good' health checks may further the debate on the ethical evaluation and possible regulation of these personal health checks. METHODS: In 2015, we interviewed twenty Dutch health check providers on criteria for 'good' health checks, and the role these criteria play in their practices. RESULTS: Providers unanimously formulate a number of minimal criteria: Checks must focus on (risk factors for) treatable/preventable disease; Tests must be reliable and clinically valid; Participation must be informed and voluntary; Checks should provide more benefits than harms; Governmental screenings should be cost-effective. Aspirational criteria mentioned were: Follow-up care should be provided; Providers should be skilled and experienced professionals that put the benefit of (potential) users first; Providers should take time and attention. Some criteria were contested: People should be free to test on any (risk factor for) disease; Health checks should only be performed in people at high risk for disease that are likely to implement health advice; Follow up care of privately funded tests should not drain on collective resources. Providers do not always fulfil their own criteria. Their reasons reveal conflicts between criteria, conflicts between criteria and other ethical values, and point to components in the (Dutch) organisation of health care that hinder an ethical provision of health checks. Moreover, providers consider informed consent a criterion that is hard to establish in practice. CONCLUSIONS: According to providers, personal health checks should meet the same criteria as population screenings, with the exception of cost-effectiveness. Providers do not always fulfil their own criteria. Results indicate that in thinking about the ethics of health checks potential conflicts between criteria and underlying values should be explicated, guidance in weighing of criteria should be provided and the larger context should be taken into account: other actors than providers need to take up responsibility, and ideally benefits and harms of health checks should be weighed against other measures targeting (risk factors for) disease.


Subject(s)
Health Knowledge, Attitudes, Practice , Health Personnel/ethics , Mass Screening/ethics , Primary Prevention/ethics , Cardiovascular Diseases/prevention & control , Cost-Benefit Analysis , Female , Health Status Indicators , Humans , Informed Consent , Interviews as Topic , Male , Metabolic Diseases/prevention & control , Neoplasms/prevention & control , Patient Acceptance of Health Care , Primary Prevention/standards , Qualitative Research
3.
Fam Cancer ; 12(2): 319-24, 2013 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23535968

ABSTRACT

The diagnosis of Lynch syndrome can lead to the prevention of colorectal cancer through periodic colonoscopies and removal of premalignant lesions in susceptible individuals. Therefore, predisposed individuals identified by mutation analysis are advised to inform their at-risk relatives about the options of predictive DNA testing and preventive measures. However, it has now been established that more than half of these relatives do not receive the necessary information. Barriers in conveying information include family communication problems and variable attitudes and practice among clinical geneticists. In this complex field, both medical, psychological, ethical and juridical aspects deserve consideration. Here we summarize the development of a revised guideline for clinical geneticists that allows a more active role of the geneticist, aimed at improving procedures to inform family members in Lynch syndrome and other hereditary and familial cancer syndromes.


Subject(s)
Colorectal Neoplasms, Hereditary Nonpolyposis/genetics , Duty to Warn , Family , Genetic Predisposition to Disease/genetics , Duty to Warn/ethics , Duty to Warn/psychology , Humans
4.
Eur J Hum Genet ; 20(9): 911-6, 2012 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22453292

ABSTRACT

The arrival of new genetic technologies that allow efficient examination of the whole human genome (microarray, next-generation sequencing) will impact upon both laboratories (cytogenetic and molecular genetics in the first instance) and clinical/medical genetic services. The interpretation of analytical results in terms of their clinical relevance and the predicted health status poses a challenge to both laboratory and clinical geneticists, due to the wealth and complexity of the information obtained. There is a need to discuss how to best restructure the genetic services logistically and to determine the clinical utility of genetic testing so that patients can receive appropriate advice and genetic testing. To weigh up the questions and challenges of the new genetic technologies, the European Society of Human Genetics (ESHG) held a series of workshops on 10 June 2010 in Gothenburg. This was part of an ESHG satellite symposium on the 'Changing landscape of genetic testing', co-organized by the ESHG Genetic Services Quality and Public and Professional Policy Committees. The audience consisted of a mix of geneticists, ethicists, social scientists and lawyers. In this paper, we summarize the discussions during the workshops and present some of the identified ways forward to improve and adapt the genetic services so that patients receive accurate and relevant information. This paper covers ethics, clinical utility, primary care, genetic services and the blurring boundaries between healthcare and research.


Subject(s)
Biomedical Research/trends , Genetic Testing/trends , Biomedical Research/ethics , Biomedical Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Biomedical Research/methods , Delivery of Health Care/ethics , Genetic Testing/ethics , Genetic Testing/legislation & jurisprudence , Genetic Testing/methods , High-Throughput Nucleotide Sequencing , Humans , Laboratories/ethics , Practice Guidelines as Topic
5.
J Med Ethics ; 36(7): 391-5, 2010 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-20605992

ABSTRACT

If a hereditary predisposition to colorectal cancer or breast cancer is diagnosed, most guidelines state that clinical geneticists should request index patients to inform their at-risk relatives about the existence of this condition in their family, thus enabling them to consider presymptomatic genetic testing. Those identified as mutation carriers can undertake strategies to reduce their risk of developing the disease or to facilitate early diagnosis. This procedure of informing relatives through the index patient has been criticised, as it results in relatively few requests for genetic testing, conceivably because a certain number of relatives remain uninformed. This pilot study explored attitudes toward informing family members and relevant practices among clinical geneticists. In general, clinical geneticists consider it to be in the interests of family members to be informed and acknowledge that this goal is not accomplished by current procedures. The reasons given for maintaining present practices despite this include clinical 'mores', uncertainty about the legal right of doctors to inform family members themselves, and, importantly, a lack of resources. We discuss these reasons from an ethical point of view and conclude that they are partly uninformed and inconsistent. If informing relatives is considered to be in their best interests, clinical geneticists should consider informing relatives themselves. In the common situation in which index patients do not object to informing relatives, no legal obstacles prevent geneticists from doing so. An evaluation of these findings among professionals may lead to a more active approach in clinical practice.


Subject(s)
Attitude of Health Personnel , Genetic Predisposition to Disease , Genetics, Medical , Health Knowledge, Attitudes, Practice , Neoplasms/genetics , Truth Disclosure , Family , Genetic Services , Genetic Testing , Genetics, Medical/ethics , Humans , Netherlands , Physician's Role , Pilot Projects
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...