Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 10 de 10
Filter
Add more filters










Publication year range
1.
J Law Med Ethics ; 49(4): 599-610, 2021.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35006047

ABSTRACT

In most U.S. jurisdictions, clinicians providing informal "curbside" consults are protected from medical malpractice liability due to the absence of a doctor-patient relationship. A recent Minnesota Supreme Court case, Warren v. Dinter, offers the opportunity to reassess whether the majority rule is truly serving the best interests of patients.


Subject(s)
Clinical Medicine , Malpractice , Humans , Liability, Legal , Physician-Patient Relations , Referral and Consultation
2.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 50(5): 44-45, 2020 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33095488

ABSTRACT

This book review essay discusses Birth Rights and Wrongs: How Medicine and Technology Are Remaking Reproduction and the Law (2019), by Dov Fox.

3.
AMA J Ethics ; 21(1): E50-57, 2019 01 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30672419

ABSTRACT

How to provide good care to uninsured undocumented immigrants who are broadly excluded from federally funded health benefits in the United States can raise ethical challenges for clinicians. The chilling effect of current immigration enforcement policies on health care access affects other immigrant populations and US citizens in mixed-status families. In the current political environment, students in health professions, house staff and other early career professionals, and teachers and mentors in health care settings that serve low-income immigrant populations need a shared understanding of how to provide good care under changing and challenging conditions. This article suggests key resources for clinical teaching and learning and for self-directed learning and reflection, with special attention to the "public charge" rule and its effects on immigrant health.


Subject(s)
Education, Medical , Undocumented Immigrants , Education, Medical/methods , Health Services Accessibility/ethics , Humans , Law Enforcement , Safety-net Providers , United States
4.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 48 Suppl 4: S2-S5, 2018 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30584863

ABSTRACT

This special report is published in commemoration of the fiftieth anniversary of the "Report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death," a landmark document that proposed a new way to define death, with implications that advanced the field of organ transplantation. This remarkable success notwithstanding, the concept has raised lasting questions about what it means to be dead. Is death defined in terms of the biological failure of the organism to maintain integrated functioning? Can death be declared on the basis of severe neurological injury even when biological functions remain intact? Is death essentially a social construct that can be defined in different ways, based on human judgment? These issues, and more, are discussed and debated in this report by leading experts in the field, many of whom have been engaged with this topic for decades.


Subject(s)
Bioethical Issues , Brain Death/diagnosis , Death , Organ Transplantation , Attitude to Death , Consensus , Ethics, Medical , Humans , Organ Transplantation/ethics , Organ Transplantation/methods , Organ Transplantation/psychology , Organ Transplantation/trends , Social Perception
5.
Semin Perinatol ; 42(8): 508-514, 2018 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30389228

ABSTRACT

In this commentary, we raise concerns about the compassionate use of CRISPR-mediated gene therapies in pediatric and perinatal patients. There is already a precedent for obtaining gene therapies for pediatric patients through compassionate use programs, and the recent passage of a federal Right to Try law may contribute to an increase in the number of patients who seek access to investigational products outside of a clinical trial. Clinicians, nurses, drug companies, and parents need support as they grapple with whether compassionate use of CRISPR-mediated gene therapies is the right thing to pursue for a child. We raise three issues to consider in that decision: (1) the effects of compassionate use on scientific research; (2) hype and harms of gene therapies; and (3) the limits and scope of parental authority.


Subject(s)
CRISPR-Cas Systems , Compassionate Use Trials/ethics , Ethical Analysis , Genetic Therapy/ethics , Leukemia/therapy , Decision Making , Humans , Infant , Leukemia/genetics , Leukemia/immunology , Pediatrics , Remission Induction , Treatment Outcome
6.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 48 Suppl 2: S39-S41, 2018 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30133728

ABSTRACT

The possible integration of genomic sequencing (including whole-genome and whole-exome sequencing) into the three contexts addressed in this special report-state-mandated screening programs, clinical care, and direct-to-consumer services-raises related but distinct legal issues. This essay will outline the legal issues surrounding the integration of genomic sequencing into state newborn screening programs, parental rights to refuse and access sequencing for their newborns in clinical and direct-to-consumer care, and privacy-related legal issues attending the use of sequencing in newborns.


Subject(s)
Genetic Testing/legislation & jurisprudence , Neonatal Screening/legislation & jurisprudence , Neonatal Screening/methods , Whole Genome Sequencing/standards , Confidentiality , Genetic Testing/ethics , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Neonatal Screening/ethics , Parents/psychology , United States , Whole Genome Sequencing/ethics
7.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 48(4): inside back cover, 2018 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35227032

ABSTRACT

For the past year, many around the world have said, "Me Too." Women, trans folks, and increasingly men have shared their experiences of sexual assault, harassment, and unhealthy power dynamics in their personal and professional relationships. These experiences were not a surprise to people in bioethics, especially as they relate to the control of women's bodies and behaviors that we have observed in medicine, law, and society. In The Hastings Center's work in reproductive contexts, I have learned about women whose reproductive decisions or choices are negatively affected by external forces-either by restrictive laws and policies, explicit counsel from their physicians, or implicit pressures placed on them by society. Any person with a uterus can be forced to take contraceptives if they want access to other medications that could harm a fetus, even when they are not sexually active with men. And some women of color are criminalized for miscarriages. How can those of us working in reproductive ethics be even more attentive to these experiences and to the impact of gendered power dynamics on reproductive decision-making?

8.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 47 Suppl 3: S2-S5, 2017 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29171884

ABSTRACT

Respect for autonomy is a central value in reproductive ethics, but it can be a challenge to fulfill and is sometimes an outright puzzle to understand. If a woman requests the transfer of two, three, or four embryos during fertility treatment, is that request truly autonomous, and do clinicians disrespect her if they question that decision or refuse to carry it out? Add a commitment to justice to the mix, and the challenge can become more complex still. Is it unfair for insurance policies to exclude from coverage the costs of giving fertility to those who lack it or restoring fertility in those who have lost it? What does "just reproduction" look like in the face of multifarious understandings of both justice and autonomy and in light of increasingly complex and costly reproductive technologies? In today's dialogue about reproduction, medicine, and ethics in the United States, old ethical issues-such as whether women ought to be allowed to access pregnancy termination-are more contested than they have been in decades, while new technologies-like those used to edit the genes of human embryos-suggest that our species could face unprecedented questions about who should exist. As we considered the discussions accompanying these issues and contemplated a special report responding to them, we found ourselves consistently circling back to two ethical commitments: respect for autonomy and the pursuit of justice. As one of the nine essays in this collection asks, why should certain women receive help to establish a pregnancy while others are thrown in jail when they miscarry or their child is stillborn? Respect for autonomy is required where individuals have the ability to make fully informed and voluntary choices. Yet does respecting autonomy require acceding to all the choices of patients or consumers of medical care? We consider these and related questions in this special report from the Hastings Center Report.


Subject(s)
Personal Autonomy , Reproductive Rights , Social Justice , Bioethics , Female , Humans , United States
9.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 47 Suppl 3: S6-S11, 2017 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29171894

ABSTRACT

In a project The Hastings Center is now running on the future of prenatal testing, we are encountering clear examples, both in established law and in the practices of individual providers, of failures to respect women's reproductive autonomy: when testing is not offered to certain demographics of women, for instance, or when the choices of women to terminate or continue pregnancies are prohibited or otherwise not supported. But this project also raises puzzles for reproductive autonomy. We have learned that some clinicians and patients do not discuss the fact that prenatal testing can lead to a decision about whether to terminate a pregnancy-they just don't talk about it. And while the decision whether to agree to prenatal screening and diagnostic testing is to be made with women's free and informed consent, many screening tests have been routinized in such a way that some women do not even recall agreeing to testing, while others feel that agreeing to testing is what their clinicians expect of them or that the testing is necessary to protect themselves and their families from the significant financial hardship of raising a child with a disability. In the face of these pressures, can one really say that women are freely choosing to undergo testing or are freely choosing to continue or terminate a pregnancy following receipt of test results? The reality of these pressures is requiring us to consider expanding the scope of our investigation beyond the clinical encounter to the broader context-to think harder about what reproductive autonomy means and how best to enhance it.


Subject(s)
Personal Autonomy , Reproductive Rights , Female , Humans
10.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 46(6): inside front cover, 2016 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27875644

ABSTRACT

I joined The Hastings Center this past summer, after graduating from Duke University, where I researched advancements in neuroscience and genomics and their import for law, ethics, and policy. This research required, to an extent, faith in the idea that researchers can identify pathways by which genes combine with epigenetic and environmental factors to affect neuronal activity and influence behaviors. Throughout my first months here, I have puzzled over broad critiques of "genomic hype" in recent literature, which clash with the optimistic rhetoric found in the Human Genome Project and the Precision Medicine Initiative.


Subject(s)
Biomedical Research/ethics , Genome, Human , Genomics/ethics , Bioethical Issues , Human Genome Project/ethics , Humans , Precision Medicine/ethics
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...