Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 88
Filter
2.
Anesthesiol Clin ; 42(3): 357-366, 2024 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39054012

ABSTRACT

Facing ethical dilemmas is challenging and sometimes becomes a real burden for anesthesiologists, particularly because they rarely have previous or long-standing patient relationships that help inform clinical decision-making. Although there is no ideal algorithm that can fit all clinical situations, some basic moral and ethical principles, which should be part of every clinician's armamentarium, can guide the decision-making process. Dealing with conflicting views among providers and/or patients can be distressing but can lead to meaningful professional and personal growth for each clinician.


Subject(s)
Anesthesiologists , Humans , Anesthesiologists/ethics , Anesthesia/ethics , Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesiology/ethics , Anesthesiology/methods , Ethics, Medical , Clinical Decision-Making/ethics
3.
Anesthesiol Clin ; 42(3): 433-443, 2024 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39054018

ABSTRACT

Because modern surgical and medical care have advanced, patients increasingly present for procedural and surgical intervention with life-limiting diagnoses and/or advanced care goals such as "do not resuscitate." Anesthesiologists now care for these patients across the complete perioperative setting and frequently find themselves at the crossroads of these mounting pressures. As the boundaries and capabilities of anesthetic care and critical care anesthesiology expand so too do the specialty's needs for support in ethical decision-making. Herein, we review the role of the ethics consultation in anesthesia practice and special ethic issues encountered by the anesthesiologist.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia , Anesthesiology , Ethics Consultation , Humans , Anesthesia/ethics , Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesiology/ethics , Anesthesiologists/ethics
4.
Anesthesiol Clin ; 42(3): 473-490, 2024 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39054021

ABSTRACT

Some practices require mandatory preoperative laboratory testing for select patients presenting for anesthesia and surgery. Such mandatory preanesthesia laboratory testing has significant ethical implications related to informed consent and patient autonomy. Assumptions that a patient provides "presumed consent" by merely presenting for a test are flawed because such consents are often not informed and do not acknowledge patient autonomy. By placing a condition on access to a medical treatment, mandatory preanesthesia testing may not be ethically justifiable. Not all laboratory tests are "ethically equal"; several raise specific questions regarding informed consent, related to their potential to cause significant harm.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia , Informed Consent , Preoperative Care , Humans , Preoperative Care/ethics , Preoperative Care/methods , Anesthesia/ethics , Informed Consent/ethics , Mandatory Testing/ethics
5.
Curr Opin Anaesthesiol ; 37(4): 432-438, 2024 Aug 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38841922

ABSTRACT

PURPOSE OF REVIEW: This review explores the intricacies of ethical anesthesia, exploring the necessity for precision anesthesia and its impact on patient-reported outcomes. The primary objective is to advocate for a defined aim, promoting the implementation of rules and feedback systems. The ultimate goal is to enhance precision anesthesia care, ensuring patient safety through the implementation of a teamwork and the integration of feedback mechanisms. RECENT FINDINGS: Recent strategies in the field of anesthesia have evolved from intraoperative monitorization to a wider perioperative patient-centered precision care. Nonetheless, implementing this approach encounters significant obstacles. The article explores the evidence supporting the need for a defined aim and applicable rules for precision anesthesia's effectiveness. The implementation of the safety culture is underlined. The review delves into the teamwork description with structured feedback systems. SUMMARY: Anesthesia is a multifaceted discipline that involves various stakeholders. The primary focus is delivering personalized precision care. This review underscores the importance of establishing clear aims, defined rules, and fostering effective and well tolerated teamwork with accurate feedback for improving patient-reported outcomes. The Safe Brain Initiative approach, emphasizing algorithmic monitoring and systematic follow-up, is crucial in implementing a fundamental and standardized reporting approach within patient-centered anesthesia care practice.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia , Patient-Centered Care , Humans , Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesia/standards , Anesthesia/ethics , Anesthesia/adverse effects , Patient-Centered Care/ethics , Patient-Centered Care/standards , Anesthesiology/ethics , Anesthesiology/standards , Patient Safety/standards , Precision Medicine/methods , Precision Medicine/ethics , Precision Medicine/standards , Patient Care Team/ethics , Patient Care Team/standards , Patient Care Team/organization & administration , Patient Reported Outcome Measures , Monitoring, Intraoperative/methods , Monitoring, Intraoperative/standards
6.
J Clin Ethics ; 35(2): 93-100, 2024.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38728693

ABSTRACT

AbstractObjective: We performed this study to examine patients' choices to permit or refuse medical student pelvic examinations under anesthesia (EUAs) during planned gynecologic procedures. DESIGN: We conducted an exploratory retrospective chart review of electronic consent forms at a single academic medical center using contingency tables, logistic regression, and nonparametric tests to explore relationships between patient and physician characteristics and consent. RESULTS: We identified and downloaded electronic consent forms for a census of 4,000 patients undergoing gynecologic surgery from September 2020 through calendar year 2022. Forms were linked to anonymized medical record information. Of the 4,000 patients, 142 (3.6%) were removed from analysis because consent forms were incomplete. Of 3,858 patients, 308 (8.0%) were asked for EUA consent more than once, 46 of whom were not consistent. Overall, 3,308 (85.7%) patients consented every time asked, and 550 (14.2%) refused or limited EUA consent at least once. Nine patients limited their consent to female students, and two patients refused medical student participation at all. We performed exploratory multiple logistic regression analyses exploring differences in rates of consent across patient and physician demographic groups. CONCLUSIONS: We find that some patients are more likely than others to refuse a pelvic EUA, magnifying the dignitary harm from a nonconsensual invasion of intimate bodily integrity and perpetuating historic wrongs visited upon vulnerable people of color and religious minorities. Patients' rights to respect and control over their bodies require that physicians take seriously the ethical obligation to inform their patients and ask them for permission.


Subject(s)
Gynecological Examination , Informed Consent , Students, Medical , Humans , Female , Retrospective Studies , Adult , Middle Aged , Anesthesia/ethics , Male , Gynecologic Surgical Procedures , Aged
7.
Br J Anaesth ; 132(6): 1184-1186, 2024 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38729742

ABSTRACT

The changing ethical and legal landscape in the UK means that anaesthetists should routinely be discussing the risk of death during the consent process. To do this effectively means expanding anaesthetic preassessment services for children and young people, something that has been recognised as a priority, but which still needs investment and an appreciation of its value at the trust level.


Subject(s)
Informed Consent , Preoperative Care , Humans , Child , Preoperative Care/methods , Adolescent , United Kingdom , Anesthesia/ethics
8.
Paediatr Anaesth ; 34(8): 689-696, 2024 Aug.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38738763

ABSTRACT

Children commonly refuse induction of anesthesia. Anesthesia providers must then decide whether to honor the child's dissent or to proceed over objection. In some circumstances, a forced induction involves restraining the child, incurring both practical and ethical harms to the patient-provider encounter. This educational review explores the practical dilemma encountered when a child dissents to induction of anesthesia. In the course of exploring this dilemma, dissent and associated terms are defined and compared, and the prominent ethical underpinnings regarding pediatric decision-making are described to clarify dissent as an ethical and practical concept. Important legal and professional standards are summarized, and practice trends are discussed to depict the current state of practice, including novel approaches to honoring pediatric dissent for elective surgeries. This information is then used to invite providers to consider where they ethically situate themselves within a legally and professionally defined space of acceptable practice. Finally, these considerations are synthesized to discuss important nuances regarding pediatric refusal, and some key questions are presented for clinicians to ponder as they consider their practice of choosing whether to honor pediatric dissent at induction.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia , Treatment Refusal , Humans , Anesthesia/ethics , Treatment Refusal/ethics , Child , Pediatrics/ethics , Decision Making/ethics , Anesthesiology/ethics , Anesthesiology/education
9.
Acta bioeth ; 28(2): 281-289, oct. 2022. tab
Article in English | LILACS | ID: biblio-1402935

ABSTRACT

Abstract: In the literature Informed consent (IC) assumptions is well established. However, the different stages and the conditions under which the IC for anesthetic practices is obtained, is scarce. The aim of the present study is to explore the phases and conditions of IC in anesthesiology. Anonymized clinical records of 325 patients submitted to anesthetic procedures at the Institute of Oncology of Porto were analyzed. A total agreement between the anesthetic techniques established in the IC and those performed, was reach with 270 patients. The importance of IC in clinical practice is discussed and an ideal process for IC is argued.


Resumen: El consentimiento informado (CI) está bien establecido en la literatura. Sin embargo, la información sobre las diferentes fases y condiciones en las que se obtiene el CI para las prácticas anestésicas es escasa. El objetivo del presente estudio es explorar las fases y condiciones de obtención de la CI en anestesiología. Se analizaron las historias clínicas anónimas de 325 pacientes sometidos a procedimientos anestésicos en el Instituto de Oncología de Oporto. Se alcanzó una concordancia total entre las técnicas de anestesia establecidas en el CI y las realizadas con 270 pacientes. Se defiende la importancia del CI en la práctica clínica y se discute un proceso ideal para obtenerlo.


Resumo: Na literatura o Consentimento Informado (CI) é bem estabelecido. Contudo, a informação sobre as diferentes fases e as condições em que o CI para práticas anestésicas é obtido, é escassa. O objetivo do presente estudo é explorar as fases e condições da obtenção do CI em anestesiologia. Foram analisados os registos clínicos anónimos de 325 pacientes submetidos a procedimentos anestésicos no Instituto de Oncologia do Porto. Foi alcançado um acordo total entre as técnicas anestésicas estabelecidas no CI e as realizadas, com 270 pacientes. A importância do CI na prática clínica é defendida e discute-se um processo ideal para a obtenção do CI.


Subject(s)
Humans , Male , Female , Adult , Middle Aged , Aged , Aged, 80 and over , Young Adult , Informed Consent/ethics , Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesia/ethics , Anesthesiology/ethics
10.
BMJ Open ; 12(7): e059189, 2022 07 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35777881

ABSTRACT

INTRODUCTION: This study aims to identify the full spectrum of ethical challenges of all forms of palliative sedation for adults as presented in current clinical practice guidelines (CPGs) and to determine whether CPGs specify ethical challenges of this therapy for patients with cancer and non-cancer and, if so, how exactly they do this. To the best of our knowledge, no studies have yet investigated this topic. The purpose is purely descriptive; our aim is not to make any kind of normative judgements on these challenges. Nor is our aim to assess the quality of the CPGs. METHODS AND ANALYSIS: We will perform a systematic review of CPGs on palliative sedation for adults via five electronic databases, grey literature search tools, citation tracking and contact with palliative care experts. Current CPGs accredited by an international, national or regional authority, published in English, German, French, Italian or Polish, from 2000 to the date of the search, will be subjected to content analysis at the textual, linguistic and thematic levels. ETHICS AND DISSEMINATION: This is a protocol for a systematic review and no human will be involved in this research. Therefore, ethics approval and consent to participate are not applicable to this context. This study protocol is reported in accordance with the Preferred Reporting Items for Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis for Protocols criteria and registered on PROSPERO. Moreover, the integral version of this study protocol is published as a preprint on Research Square. The results of this study will be actively disseminated through peer-reviewed journals and books, international, national and local conference presentations, social media and media in general.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia , Palliative Care , Adult , Anesthesia/ethics , Humans , Palliative Care/ethics , Practice Guidelines as Topic , Systematic Reviews as Topic
11.
Anesth Analg ; 130(6): 1474-1481, 2020 06.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32384337

ABSTRACT

Frailty is present in more than 30% of individuals older than 65 years of age presenting for anesthesia and surgery, and poses a number of unique issues in the informed consent process. Much attention has been directed at the increased incidence of poor outcomes in these individuals, including postoperative mortality, complications, and prolonged length of stay. These material risks are not generally factored into conventional risk predictors, so it is likely that individuals with frailty are never fully informed of the true risk for procedures undertaken in the hospital setting. While the term "frailty" has the advantage of alerting to risk and allowing appropriate care and interventions, the term has the social disadvantage of encouraging objectivity to ageism. This may encourage paternalistic behavior from carers and family encroaching on self-determination and, in extreme cases, manifesting as coercion and compromising autonomy. There is a high prevalence of neurocognitive disorder in frail elderly patients, and care must be taken to identify those without capacity to provide informed consent; equally important is to not exclude those with capacity from providing consent. Obtaining consent for research adds an extra onus to that of clinical consent. The informed consent process in the frail elderly poses unique challenges to the busy clinical anesthesiologist. At the very least, an increased time commitment should be recognized. The gap between theoretical goals and actual practice of informed consent should be acknowledged.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia/adverse effects , Anesthesia/ethics , Frailty/surgery , Informed Consent , Aged , Ageism , Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesiology/legislation & jurisprudence , Biomedical Research/trends , Ethics, Research , Frail Elderly , Frailty/complications , Frailty/psychology , Humans , Length of Stay , Neurocognitive Disorders/complications , Outcome Assessment, Health Care , Preoperative Period , Prevalence , Risk
12.
J Med Philos ; 45(1): 16-27, 2020 01 10.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31841148

ABSTRACT

Christopher Boorse is very skeptical of there being a pathocentric internal morality of medicine. Boorse argues that doctors have always engaged in activities other than healing, and so no internal morality of medicine can provide objections to euthanasia, contraception, sterilization, and other practices not aimed at fighting pathologies. Objections to these activities have to come from outside of medicine. I first argue that Boorse fails to appreciate that such widespread practices are compatible with medicine being essentially pathocentric. Then I contend that the pathocentric essence, properly understood, does not prohibit physicians from engaging in actions that are not aimed at combating pathologies, but rather supports an internal morality of medicine that allows medical providers to refuse without penalty to engage in practices that promote pathologies.


Subject(s)
Ethics, Medical , Morals , Anesthesia/ethics , Contraception/ethics , Euthanasia/ethics , Humans , Philosophy, Medical , Social Responsibility
15.
BMC Med Ethics ; 20(1): 14, 2019 02 18.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30777063

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Animal-derived constituents are frequently used in anaesthesia and surgery, and patients are seldom informed of this. This is problematic for a growing minority of patients who may have religious or secular concerns about their use in their care. It is not currently common practice to inform patients about the use of animal-derived constituents, yet what little empirical data does exist indicates that many patients want the opportunity to give their informed consent. DISCUSSION: First we review the nature and scale of the problem by looking at the groups who may have concerns about the use of animal-derived constituents in their care. We then summarise some of the products used in anaesthesia and surgery that can contain such constituents, such as anaesthetic drugs, surgical implants and dressings. Finally, we explore the problem of animal-derived constituents and consent using Beauchamp and Childress' four principles approach, examining issues of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence and justice. Disclosing the use of animal-derived constituents in anaesthesia and surgery is warranted under Beauchamp and Childress' four principles approach to the problem. Although there exist systemic and practical challenges to implementing this in practice, the ethical case for doing so is strong. The Montgomery ruling presents additional legal reason for disclosure because it entails that patients must be made aware of risks associated with their treatment that they attach significance to.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia/ethics , Anesthesia/methods , Disclosure/ethics , Informed Consent/ethics , Animal Welfare/ethics , Animals , Beneficence , Biocompatible Materials/chemistry , Diet, Vegan/ethics , Ethical Theory , Humans , Personal Autonomy , Pharmaceutical Preparations , Principle-Based Ethics , Religion and Medicine , Vegetarians
16.
Acta Med Port ; 32(1): 53-60, 2019 Feb 01.
Article in Portuguese | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30753804

ABSTRACT

INTRODUCTION: Informed consent is an active process of the doctor-patient relationship, based on ethical and legal principles. The anesthetic act has inherent risks, which should be subject of specific consent. The aim of this study was to evaluate the degree of implementation of written specific informed consent for anesthesia in the context of elective surgery. MATERIAL AND METHODS: An observational prospective study, at a tertiary university hospital, in 230 patients aged 60 years or older, undergoing elective surgery between May and July 2017. Eligible patients who consented to participate were interviewed clinically on the day before surgery. In the postoperative period, the anesthetic technique and the existence of the written informed consent for the anesthetic and surgical procedures were assessed. Patients who were unable to give informed consent or those admitted in the Intensive Care Unit after surgery were excluded. RESULTS: Written informed consent for the surgical procedure was obtained for 225 (97.8%), while it was obtained in just 96 (41.7%) patients for the anesthetic act. There was a higher prevalence of stroke, anemia, and higher Charlson and physical American Society of Anesthesiologists scores in patients without written informed consent for the anesthetic act. DISCUSSION: We identified a low implementation of written informed consent for anesthesia. This situation may have important implications in the context of disciplinary, civil or criminal liability. CONCLUSION: Despite its importance, the practice of written informed consent for anesthesia in this institution is not yet implemented on a regular basis.


Introdução: O consentimento informado é um processo ativo na relação médico-doente, assente em valores éticos e legais. O ato anestésico tem riscos inerentes, que devem ser alvo de consentimento específico. O objetivo deste estudo foi avaliar o grau de implementação do consentimento informado escrito para o ato anestésico no contexto de cirurgia eletiva. Material e Métodos: Estudo observacional prospetivo, num hospital terciário e universitário, em 230 doentes com idade igual ou superior a 60 anos submetidos a cirurgia eletiva entre maio e julho de 2017. Aos doentes elegíveis que consentiram participar, foi realizada entrevista clínica no dia prévio à cirurgia. No pós-operatório, foi averiguada a técnica anestésica realizada, e a existência do consentimento informado por escrito para o ato anestésico e cirúrgico. Doentes incapazes de dar consentimento informado ou admitidos na unidade de cuidados intensivos após cirurgia foram excluídos. Resultados: Em 225 (97,8%) dos doentes, verificou-se a obtenção, por escrito, do consentimento informado para o ato cirúrgico, mas apenas em 96 (41,7%) verificou-se a obtenção por escrito do consentimento informado para o ato anestésico. De entre os doentes sem registo de consentimento informado para o ato anestésico, foram mais prevalentes antecedentes de acidente vascular cerebral, anemia e scores de Charlson e de estado físico conforme à Sociedade Americana de Anestesiologia mais elevados. Discussão: Identificámos uma baixa implementação do consentimento informado escrito para o ato anestésico. Esta situação pode ter importantes implicações em contexto de responsabilidade disciplinar, civil ou penal. Conclusão: Apesar da sua importância, a prática do consentimento informado escrito para o ato anestésico nesta instituição não está implementada regularmente.


Subject(s)
Anesthesia/methods , Anesthesia/statistics & numerical data , Elective Surgical Procedures/statistics & numerical data , Informed Consent/statistics & numerical data , Aged , Anemia , Anesthesia/ethics , Elective Surgical Procedures/ethics , Elective Surgical Procedures/legislation & jurisprudence , Female , Humans , Male , Middle Aged , Prospective Studies , Severity of Illness Index , Stroke
19.
Rev. chil. anest ; 46(1): 14-18, abr. 2017.
Article in Spanish | LILACS | ID: biblio-869692

ABSTRACT

Anesthesiologists may deal with ethical dilemmas when looking after Not To Be Resuscitated (NTBR) patients. Sometimes the latters are scheduled to undergo surgical procedures that are palliative in nature. With the advent of the cardio pulmonary resuscitation in the 1960s, new problems arose, such as long resuscitations, quality of life impairment and unnecessary protracted agony. Besides the fear to death and suffering, resuscitation’s dread appeared. In the beginning, the decisión to reject the resuscitation was the physician’s responsability. The development of the Patient Self-Determination Act (PSDA) transfered to the patient or to his/her legal surrogates the right to decide about his/her medical treatment, specially at the end of life. This article revised the evolution that allowed to exercise the patient autonomy, as well as the best way to proceed when anesthesia and surgery are necessary to care for a patient with a Do Not Resuscitate Order.


El anestesiólogo puede enfrentar dilemas éticos cuando debe anestesiar pacientes con indicaciones restrictivas (Límite del Esfuerzo Terapéutico, Orden de No Reanimar). Estos pacientes con frecuencia son sometidos a intervenciones destinadas a mejorar su calidad de vida, o para el control de síntomas, a pesar de tener un mal pronóstico evolutivo, y/o deterioro de su condición física. A mediados de la década de 1960, con la RCP (Reanimación Cardiopulmonar) aparecieron nuevos problemas, como reanimaciones reiteradas, deterioro de la calidad de vida, y prolongación de la agonía. Entonces, al miedo a la muerte y al sufrimiento, se sumó el miedo a la reanimación. Inicialmente, el médico responsable del paciente era el único habilitado para rechazar estas medidas de reanimación (NTBR, “not to be resuscitated”), con el subsiguiente debate bioético. Mas tarde, el desarrollo del principio de autonomía, transfirió al paciente y a su entorno más cercano el derecho a tomar decisiones informadas sobre su propio tratamiento médico1. Este artículo revisa los antecedentes relevantes que han permitido el traspaso del poder de decisión a los pacientes, así como la mejor forma de proceder ante la necesidad de administrarles anestesia cuando hay indicaciones restrictivas.


Subject(s)
Humans , Male , Middle Aged , Aged , Advance Directive Adherence , Anesthesia/ethics , Bioethical Issues , Patient Rights , Resuscitation Orders , Personal Autonomy
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL