Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 18 de 18
Filter
Add more filters











Publication year range
2.
Monash Bioeth Rev ; 38(2): 95-104, 2020 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33275190

ABSTRACT

Many controversies in bioethics turn on questions of moral status. Some moral status issues have received extensive bioethical attention, including those raised by abortion, embryo experimentation, and animal research. Beyond these established debates lie a less familiar set of moral status issues, many of which are tied to recent scientific breakthroughs. This review article surveys some key developments that raise moral status issues, including the development of in vitro brains, part-human animals, "synthetic" embryos, and artificial womb technologies. It introduces the papers in this Special Issue, contextualises their contributions to the moral status literature, and highlights some enduring challenges of determining the moral status of novel types of beings.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Animal Experimentation/ethics , Bioethical Issues , Biotechnology/ethics , Embryo Research/ethics , Moral Status , Artificial Organs/ethics , Bioethics , Brain , Dissent and Disputes , Female , Humans , Pregnancy , Uterus
3.
Med Law Rev ; 28(2): 342-374, 2020 May 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31851353

ABSTRACT

It is frequently claimed that artificial wombs (AWs) could alleviate the burdens placed exclusively on women in reproduction. In this article, I demonstrate how AWs used for the partial gestation of preterm neonates could introduce new choices for women by changing perceptions of tolerable risks in gestation. In light of advancing medical technology, it is necessary to consider whether the current legal framework in England and Wales would support increased choice for women about alternative forms of gestation. I examine the ill-defined offence of 'unlawfully procuring miscarriage' in the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 and demonstrate that different conclusions about the legal significance of ending a pregnancy are evident, depending on the analytical lens adopted in interpreting ambiguities. Furthermore, I demonstrate that the defences available to pregnancy termination under the Abortion Act 1967 are too narrow to support choices about alternative forms of gestation, even if they become physically and medically possible. Therefore, we should decriminalise termination of pregnancy, or, if it is assumed that gestation is the business of the criminal law, specific reforms to the legal framework are necessary. The offence of unlawfully procuring miscarriage is too uncertain and broad, and the defences available are too restrictive.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/legislation & jurisprudence , Artificial Organs/ethics , Ectogenesis/ethics , Pregnancy , Uterus , Abortion, Spontaneous , Criminal Law/legislation & jurisprudence , England , Female , Humans , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/ethics , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/legislation & jurisprudence , Wales
4.
Med Law Rev ; 28(1): 93-123, 2020 Feb 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31155656

ABSTRACT

English law is unambiguous that legal personality, and with it all legal rights and protections, is assigned at birth. This rule is regarded as a bright line that is easily and consistently applied. The time has come, however, for the rule to be revisited. This article demonstrates that advances in fetal surgery and (anticipated) artificial wombs do not marry with traditional conceptions of birth and being alive in law. These technologies introduce the possibility of ex utero gestation, and/or temporary existence ex utero, and consequently developing human beings that are novel to the law. Importantly, therefore, the concepts of birth and born alive no longer distinguish between human beings deserving of legal protection in the way originally intended. Thus, there is a need for reform, for a new approach to determining the legal significance of birth and what being legally alive actually encompasses. Investigating the law of birth is of crucial importance, because of the implications of affording or denying the subjects of new reproductive technologies rights and protections. A determination of the legal status of the subject of fetal surgery or an artificial womb will determine what can and cannot be done to each entity. Moreover, the status afforded to these entities will drastically impact on the freedoms of pregnant women.


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs/ethics , Fetoscopy/ethics , Jurisprudence , Live Birth , Parturition , Personhood , Uterus , Beginning of Human Life , England , Female , Humans , Pregnancy
5.
J Med Ethics ; 45(11): 728-731, 2019 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31473654

ABSTRACT

In a recent publication, I argued that there is a conceptual difference between artificial womb (AW) technology, capable of facilitating gestation ex utero, and neonatal intensive care, providing incubation to neonates born prematurely. One of the reasons I provided for this distinction was that the subjects of each process are different entities. The subject of the process of gestation ex utero is a unique human entity: a 'gestateling', rather than a fetus or a newborn preterm neonate. Nick Colgrove wrote a response to my paper, claiming that my distinction between the subject of an AW and a newborn (in intensive care) was false. He claims that I have not accounted for the proper definition of 'birth' and that gestatelings are not a distinct product of human reproduction. Further, Colgrove posits that even if I can successfully distinguish gestatelings from preterms, such a distinction is morally irrelevant because the entities would have the same moral status. In this paper, I address the three challenges raised and defend the claim that gestatelings are unique entities. Moreover, I argue that moral status should not be considered ipso facto determinative in the debate about AWs.


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs/ethics , Ectogenesis/ethics , Uterus , Bioethical Issues , Female , Fetus/physiology , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Moral Status
6.
J Med Ethics ; 45(11): 723-726, 2019 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31341012

ABSTRACT

Subjects of ectogenesis-human beings that are developing in artificial wombs (AWs)-share the same moral status as newborns. To demonstrate this, I defend two claims. First, subjects of partial ectogenesis-those that develop in utero for a time before being transferred to AWs-are newborns (in the full sense of the word). Second, subjects of complete ectogenesis-those who develop in AWs entirely-share the same moral status as newborns. To defend the first claim, I rely on Elizabeth Chloe Romanis's distinctions between fetuses, newborns and subjects of ectogenesis. For Romanis, the subject of partial ectogenesis 'is neither a fetus nor a baby' but is, instead, a 'new product of human reproduction'. In this essay, I begin by, expanding upon Romanis's argument that subjects of partial ectogenesis are not fetuses while arguing that those subjects are newborns. Next, I show that the distinction that Romanis draws between subjects of partial ectogenesis and newborns needs to be revised. The former is a kind of the latter. This leads us to an argument that shows why different moral statuses cannot be justifiably assigned to subjects of partial ectogenesis and subjects of complete ectogenesis, respectively. As subjects of partial ectogenesis share the same moral status as newborns, it follows that subjects of complete ectogenesis share the same moral status as newborns as well. Iconclude by considering implications that this essay may have for the research and development of AW technology and conceptual links between a subject's moral status and birth.


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs/ethics , Ectogenesis/ethics , Uterus , Bioethical Issues , Female , Fetus/physiology , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Moral Status
7.
J Tissue Eng Regen Med ; 13(8): 1294-1315, 2019 08.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31062444

ABSTRACT

Conventional fertility preservation methods such as oocyte or embryo cryopreservation are currently insufficient to treat including those patients with prepubertal cancer and premature ovarian failure. Ovarian tissue cryopreservation presents as an alternative but has limitations with a potential risk of reintroducing malignant cells in patients who recover from cancer, those of chemotherapy prior to tissue cryopreservation. The so called "artificial ovary" aims to resolve this issue by transplanting isolated follicles with or without a biological scaffold. The artificial ovary may also offer an effective alternative option for those who cannot benefit from traditional assisted reproductive techniques such as in vitro fertilisation. To date, in animal studies and human trial, the artificial ovary restored endocrine function, achieved in vivo follicular development, and resulted in successful pregnancies. However, development of a technique for higher follicular recovery rate and a more optimised design of delivery scaffold, better transplantation techniques to prevent postsurgical ischemia, and consideration for genetic safety are required for safer and consistent human clinical applications. Ideas from different transplantation surgeries (e.g., entire ovary, ovarian cortex, and transplantation with tissue-engineered products) can be applied to enhance the efficacy of artificial ovarian transplantation. For the better application of artificial ovary, a deeper understanding of mechanical and biochemical properties of the ovary and folliculogenesis after cryopreservation, transplantation with or without scaffold, and development of sophisticated in vivo imaging techniques of transplanted artificial ovary need to precede its efficient clinical application.


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs , Fertility Preservation , Ovary/physiology , Animals , Artificial Organs/ethics , Female , Fertility Preservation/ethics , Humans , Organ Preservation , Tissue Engineering , Tissue Scaffolds/chemistry
8.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 49(1): 3, 2019 Jan.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30790307

ABSTRACT

It is often pointed out that one cannot be "a little bit pregnant," but pregnancy's borders are no longer so crisp. At Children's Hospital of Philadelphia, scientists have created an artificial womb in which "extremely premature" lambs were nurtured for four weeks, enough to make them ready to meet the world. The goal is to advance this technology until it is available for very premature human infants. At present, we put preemies into neonatal intensive care units, which are extremely stressful for the babies and their families, and the things we do to try to support them often cause serious damage. If successful, the artificial womb could be a terrific technology. The implications are remarkable. Would humans become somewhat like marsupials? Now, one is either born or not. Would this technology create a new, intermediate stage? What would this mean ethically and legally?


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs/ethics , Uterus , Animals , Female , Fetus , Humans , Infant, Extremely Premature , Pregnancy , Sheep
9.
J Bioeth Inq ; 16(1): 61-73, 2019 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30565032

ABSTRACT

Technological advances are making devices that functionally replace body parts-artificial organs and limbs-more widely used, and more capable of providing patients with lives that are close to "normal." Some of the ethical issues this is likely to raise relate to how such prostheses are conceptualized. Prostheses are ambiguous between being inanimate objects and sharing in the status of human bodies-which already have an ambiguous status, as both objects and subjects. At the same time, the possibility of replacing body parts with artificial objects puts pressure on the normative status typically accorded to human bodies, seemingly confirming that body parts are replaceable objects. The paper argues that bodies' normative status relies on the relation of a body to a person and shows that persons could have similar relations to prostheses. This suggests that in approaching ethical issues surrounding prostheses, it is appropriate to regard them as more like body parts than like objects.


Subject(s)
Artificial Limbs/ethics , Artificial Organs/ethics , Artificial Limbs/psychology , Artificial Organs/psychology , Human Body , Humans , Mind-Body Relations, Metaphysical , Prostheses and Implants/ethics , Prostheses and Implants/psychology , Self Concept
11.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 46(6): 2, 2016 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27875641

ABSTRACT

In the current issue of The New Atlantis, Daniel Sarewitz, professor of science and society at Arizona State University, argues that science is broken because it is managed and judged by scientists themselves, operating under Vannevar Bush's famous 1945 declaration that scientific progress depends on the "free play of free intellects … dictated by their curiosity." With that scientific agenda, society ends up with a lot of unnecessary, uncoordinated, and unproductive research. To save science, holds Sarewitz, we need to put it in the hands of people who are looking for practical solutions to specific problems. In one article in this issue of the Hastings Center Report (November-December 2016), Kirstin Borgerson poses a question in this same conceptual space: are there too many clinical trials? Other pieces in the issue cover a mix of topics: the lead article addresses some of the challenges that will have to be faced as "artificial organs" become available, a third article looks at how crowdfunding sites like GoFundMe can be used to make public appeals for medical funding, and a special report found in a supplement to the issue offers a round of analysis and recommendations about the provision of medical care to professional football players.


Subject(s)
Bioethical Issues , Biomedical Research/ethics , Artificial Organs/ethics , Clinical Trials as Topic/ethics , Financing, Organized/methods , Humans
12.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 46(6): 14-24, 2016 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27875647

ABSTRACT

One day soon it may be possible to replace a failing heart, liver, or kidney with a long-lasting mechanical replacement or perhaps even with a 3-D printed version based on the patient's own tissue. Such artificial organs could make transplant waiting lists and immunosuppression a thing of the past. Supposing that this happens, what will the ongoing care of people with these implants involve? In particular, how will the need to maintain the functioning of artificial organs over an extended period affect patients and their doctors and the responsibilities of those who manufacture such devices? Drawing on lessons from the history of the cardiac pacemaker, this article offers an initial survey of the ethical issues posed by the need to maintain and service artificial organs. We briefly outline the nature and history of cardiac pacemakers, with a particular focus on the need for technical support, maintenance, and replacement of these devices. Drawing on the existing medical literature and on our conversations and correspondence with cardiologists, regulators, and manufacturers, we describe five sources of ethical issues associated with pacemaker maintenance: the location of the devices inside the human body, such that maintenance generates surgical risks; the complexity of the devices, which increases the risk of harms to patients as well as introducing potential injustices in access to treatment; the role of software-particularly software that can be remotely accessed-in the functioning of the devices, which generates privacy and security issues; the impact of continual development and improvement of the device; and the influence of commercial interests in the context of a medical device market in which there are several competing products. Finally, we offer some initial suggestions as to how these questions should be answered.


Subject(s)
Artificial Organs/ethics , Biomedical Engineering/ethics , Biomedical Research/ethics , Organ Transplantation/ethics , Biocompatible Materials , Ethics, Medical , Female , Heart, Artificial/ethics , Humans , Male , Pacemaker, Artificial , Personal Autonomy , Social Values
18.
Swiss Med Wkly ; 136(33-34): 523-8, 2006 Aug 19.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16983593

ABSTRACT

The main ethical problem of organ transplantation is the shortage of transplantable organs. The substitute strategies currently under discussion endanger frust in transplantion medicine and thereby increase the problem. Thus ethically preferable alternatives to overcome the shortage are suggested.


Subject(s)
Transplants/ethics , Transplants/supply & distribution , Artificial Organs/ethics , Humans , Living Donors/ethics , Stem Cell Transplantation/ethics , Stem Cell Transplantation/methods , Transplantation, Heterologous/ethics , Transplantation, Heterologous/methods
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL