Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 852
Filter
2.
Bioethics ; 33(1): 68-75, 2019 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30182368

ABSTRACT

In vitro gametogenesis (IVG) is believed to be the next big breakthrough in reproductive medicine. The prima facie acceptance of this possible future technology is notable when compared to the general prohibition on human reproductive cloning. After all, if safety is the main reason for not allowing reproductive cloning, one might expect a similar conclusion for the reproductive application of IVG, since both technologies hold considerable and comparable risks. However, safety concerns may be overcome, and are presumably not the sole reason why cloning is being condemned. We therefore assess the non-safety arguments against reproductive cloning, yet most of these can also be held against IVG. The few arguments that cannot be used against IVG are defective. We conclude from this that it will be hard to defend a ban on reproductive cloning while accepting the reproductive use of IVG.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/ethics , Gametogenesis , Genetic Engineering/ethics , Germ Cells , Reproduction/ethics , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/ethics , Stem Cells , Child , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Dissent and Disputes , Genetic Engineering/legislation & jurisprudence , Humans , Parents , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/legislation & jurisprudence , Social Control, Formal
3.
J Int Bioethique Ethique Sci ; 28(4): 165-184, 2018 Mar 07.
Article in French | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29561084

ABSTRACT

The hesitations on the legal classification of the embryo lead to the doctrinal realization, that there is a certainty about its status, or, that it hasn't got any which allows the creator of the standard to reify it.The access to the claims which are based on specific interests seem to be at the heart of justifications to new legal rules concerning the embryo, even if It seems there are underlying specific interests.Confronted to the state disengagement in favour of these interests, the embryo, as far as French law is concerned, the embryo falls only under a limited protection which is destined to lose authority.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryo Disposition/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryo, Mammalian , France , Humans , Personhood
4.
Hum Reprod Update ; 23(2): 156-165, 2017 03 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27852683

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Embryo splitting or twinning has been widely used in veterinary medicine over 20 years to generate monozygotic twins with desirable genetic characteristics. The first human embryo splitting, reported in 1993, triggered fierce ethical debate on human embryo cloning. Since Dolly the sheep was born in 1997, the international community has acknowledged the complexity of the moral arguments related to this research and has expressed concerns about the potential for reproductive cloning in humans. A number of countries have formulated bans either through laws, decrees or official statements. However, in general, these laws specifically define cloning as an embryo that is generated via nuclear transfer (NT) and do not mention embryo splitting. Only the UK includes under cloning both embryo splitting and NT in the same legislation. On the contrary, the Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine does not have a major ethical objection to transferring two or more artificially created embryos with the same genome with the aim of producing a single pregnancy, stating that 'since embryo splitting has the potential to improve the efficacy of IVF treatments for infertility, research to investigate the technique is ethically acceptable'. OBJECTIVE AND RATIONALE: Embryo splitting has been introduced successfully to the veterinary medicine several decades ago and today is a part of standard practice. We present here an overview of embryo splitting experiments in humans and non-human primates and discuss the potential of this technology in assisted reproduction and research. SEARCH METHODS: A comprehensive literature search was carried out using PUBMED and Google Scholar databases to identify studies on embryo splitting in humans and non-human primates. 'Embryo splitting' and 'embryo twinning' were used as the keywords, alone or in combination with other search phrases relevant to the topics of biology of preimplantation embryos. OUTCOMES: A very limited number of studies have been conducted in humans and non-human primates. The published material, especially the studies with human embryos, is controversial. Some reports suggest that twinning technology will find clinical use in reproductive medicine in the future, whereas others conclude the opposite that human twin embryos created in vitro are unsuitable not only for clinical, but also for research, purposes. WIDER IMPLICATIONS: The blastomere biopsy technique of embryo splitting seems to be unsuitable for either clinical or research purposes; however, embryo bisection, a preferable method of cloning in veterinary medicine, has not yet been tested on human embryos.


Subject(s)
Blastocyst , Embryo Transfer/methods , Twinning, Monozygotic , Animals , Cattle , Cloning, Organism/ethics , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryonic Development , Female , Humans , Infertility/therapy , Infertility/veterinary , Primates , Twins
6.
Food Drug Law J ; 71(4): 608-33, 2016.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29140647

ABSTRACT

Scientists have repurposed an adaptive immune system of single cell organisms to create a new type of gene-editing tool: CRISPR (clustered regularly interspaced short palindromic repeats)-Cas technology. Scientists in China have reported its use in the genome modification of non-viable human embryos. This has ignited a spirited debate about the moral, ethical, scientific, and social implications of human germline genome engineering. There have also been calls for regulations; however, FDA has yet to formally announce its oversight of clinical applications of CRISPR-Cas systems. This paper reviews FDA regulation of previously controversial biotechnology breakthroughs, recombinant DNA and human cloning. It then shows that FDA is well positioned to regulate CRISPR-Cas clinical applications, due to its legislative mandates, its existing regulatory frameworks for gene therapies and assisted reproductive technologies, and other considerations.


Subject(s)
CRISPR-Cas Systems/genetics , Gene Editing/legislation & jurisprudence , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Genetic Engineering/ethics , Genetic Engineering/legislation & jurisprudence , Humans , United States , United States Food and Drug Administration
7.
Am J Bioeth ; 15(12): 30-4, 2015.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26632358

ABSTRACT

Two genetic technologies capable of making heritable changes to the human genome have revived interest in, and in some quarters a very familiar panic concerning, so-called germline interventions. These technologies are: most recently the use of CRISPR/Cas9 to edit genes in non-viable IVF zygotes and Mitochondrial Replacement Therapy (MRT) the use of which was approved in principle in a landmark vote earlier this year by the United Kingdom Parliament. The possibility of using either of these techniques in humans has encountered the most violent hostility and suspicion. However it is important to be aware that much of this hostility dates back to the fears associated with In Vitro Fertilization (IVF) and other reproductive technologies and by cloning; fears which were baseless at the time concerning both IVF and cloning the use of both of which have proved to be highly beneficial to humanity and which have been effectively regulated and controlled. This paper argues that CRISPR should by pursued through researh until it is safe enough for use in humans but there is no reason to suppose at this stage that such use will be unsafe or unethical (Collins 2015).


Subject(s)
Clustered Regularly Interspaced Short Palindromic Repeats/genetics , Epigenesis, Genetic , Genetic Engineering/legislation & jurisprudence , Genetic Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Germ-Line Mutation , Informed Consent , Cloning, Organism/adverse effects , Cloning, Organism/ethics , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Fertilization in Vitro/adverse effects , Fertilization in Vitro/ethics , Fertilization in Vitro/legislation & jurisprudence , Genetic Engineering/ethics , Genetic Research/ethics , Genome, Human/genetics , Humans , Informed Consent/ethics , Informed Consent/legislation & jurisprudence , Mitochondrial Replacement Therapy/adverse effects , Mitochondrial Replacement Therapy/ethics , Mitochondrial Replacement Therapy/legislation & jurisprudence , Safety , United Kingdom
10.
Hist Philos Life Sci ; 37(3): 282-304, 2015 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26205201

ABSTRACT

This paper addresses the 1996 cloning of Dolly the sheep, locating it within a long-standing tradition of animal breeding research in Edinburgh. Far from being an end in itself, the cell-nuclear transfer experiment from which Dolly was born should be seen as a step in an investigative pathway that sought the production of medically relevant transgenic animals. By historicising Dolly, I illustrate how the birth of this sheep captures a dramatic redefinition of the life sciences, when in the 1970s and 1980s the rise of neo-liberal governments and the emergence of the biotechnology market pushed research institutions to show tangible applications of their work. Through this broader interpretative framework, the Dolly story emerges as a case study of the deep transformations of agricultural experimentation during the last third of the twentieth century. The reorganisation of laboratory practice, human resources and institutional settings required by the production of transgenic animals had unanticipated consequences. One of these unanticipated effects was that the boundaries between animal and human health became blurred. As a result of this, new professional spaces emerged and the identity of Dolly the sheep was reconfigured, from an instrument for livestock improvement in the farm to a more universal symbol of the new cloning age.


Subject(s)
Animal Experimentation/history , Animals, Genetically Modified/genetics , Breeding , Cloning, Organism/history , Sheep/genetics , Animal Experimentation/ethics , Animal Experimentation/legislation & jurisprudence , Animals , Biotechnology , Cloning, Organism/ethics , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , History, 20th Century , History, 21st Century
11.
Orv Hetil ; 156(11): 434-8, 2015 Mar.
Article in Hungarian | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25749537

ABSTRACT

Reproductive human cloning is prohibited in Hungary, as in many other countries. Therapeutic human cloning is not prohibited, just like in many other countries. Stem cell therapy is also allowed. Article III, paragraph (3) of the Hungarian basic law (constitution) strictly forbids total human cloning. Article 1 of the Additional Protocol to the Oviedo Convention, on the Prohibition of Cloning Human Beings (1998) stipulates that any intervention seeking to create a human being genetically identical to another human being, whether living or dead, is prohibited. In Hungary, according to Article 174 of the Criminal Code, total human cloning constitutes a crime. Article 180, paragraph (3) of the Hungarian Act on Health declares that embryos shall not be brought about for research purposes; research shall be conducted only on embryos brought about for reproductive purposes when this is authorized by the persons entitled to decide upon its disposal, or when the embryo is damaged. Article 180, paragraph (5) of the Hungarian Act on Health stipulates that multiple individuals who genetically conform to one another shall not be brought about. According to Article 181, paragraph (1) of the Hungarian Act on Health, an embryo used for research shall be kept alive for not longer than 14 days, not counting the time it was frozen for storage and the time period of research.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Crime , Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Stem Cell Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Wedge Argument , Criminal Law , Humans , Hungary , Public-Private Sector Partnerships/ethics , Public-Private Sector Partnerships/legislation & jurisprudence , Socioeconomic Factors
15.
Stem Cells Dev ; 22 Suppl 1: 46-9, 2013 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24304075

ABSTRACT

The promise and potential of stem cell research is apparent. However, ethical questions still linger. There is as yet no consensus in the U.S. Congress on how to address the issue of reproductive cloning and media confusion of this and the quite separate issue of therapeutic cloning inhibits therapeutic advance. This paper outlines the need for the FDA to undertake a deliberate process, with input from all stakeholders, to authoritatively establish its jurisdiction over human reproductive cloning so as to foster the life-saving potential of therapeutic cloning.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Reproduction , United States Food and Drug Administration/legislation & jurisprudence , Humans , United States
17.
An. R. Acad. Farm ; 79(2): 241-252, abr.-jun. 2013.
Article in Spanish | IBECS | ID: ibc-114193

ABSTRACT

En el presente trabajo se analiza el estado actual de las investigaciones para la obtención de embriones humanos clónicos por transferencia nuclear de células somáticas y de las células troncales embrionarias y su posible utilización con fines terapéuticos. Se analizan algunos aspectos éticos y legales referentes a la obtención y utilización de los embriones humanos clónicos (AU)


Present investigations carried out to produce human embryos by somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT embryos) and nuclear transfer human embryo stem cells (NT-ESC) and their use in regenerative medicine are analyzed. Ethical and legal aspects are discussed (AU)


Subject(s)
Humans , Male , Female , Cloning, Organism/ethics , Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Cloning, Organism/methods , Embryo Research/ethics , Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Cell- and Tissue-Based Therapy/methods , Cloning, Organism/instrumentation , Cloning, Organism/trends , Cloning, Organism , Research Embryo Creation/ethics , Research Embryo Creation/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryonic Stem Cells
19.
Med Health Care Philos ; 16(4): 825-41, 2013 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23361414

ABSTRACT

This paper explores how current United States policies for funding nonreproductive cloning are justified and argues against that justification. I show that a common conceptual framework underlies the national prohibition on the use of public funds for cloning research, which I call the simple argument. This argument rests on two premises: that research harming human embryos is unethical and that embryos produced via fertilization are identical to those produced via cloning. In response to the simple argument, I challenge the latter premise. I demonstrate there are important ontological differences between human embryos (produced via fertilization) and clone embryos (produced via cloning). After considering the implications my argument has for the morality of publicly funding cloning for potential therapeutic purposes and potential responses to my position, I conclude that such funding is not only ethically permissible, but also humane national policy.


Subject(s)
Cloning, Organism/legislation & jurisprudence , Financing, Government/legislation & jurisprudence , Cloning, Organism/ethics , Federal Government , Financing, Government/ethics , Humans , Policy Making , United States
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...