Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 119
Filtrar
1.
J Law Med ; 31(1): 122-129, 2024 May.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38761393

RESUMO

In Australia, there are only two publicly reported disciplinary cases against specialist medical administrators. In the most recent decision of Medical Board of Australia v Gruner, the Victorian Civil and Administrative Tribunal confirmed that specialist medical administrators owe patients and the public the same professional obligations as medical practitioners with direct patient contact. More controversially, the Tribunal also held that medical administrators have a professional obligation only to accept roles with clear position descriptions that afford them sufficient time and resources to ensure the safe delivery of health services. We argue that this imposes unrealistic expectations on medical administrators engaged by rural, regional, or private health services that already struggle to attract and retain specialist medical expertise. This may exacerbate existing health inequalities by disincentivising specialist medical administrators from seeking fractional appointments that assist under-funded areas of workforce shortage.


Assuntos
Diretores Médicos , Humanos , Austrália , Especialização
2.
J Law Med Ethics ; 52(1): 101-117, 2024.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38818593

RESUMO

Secondary use of clinical data in research or learning activities (SeConts) has the potential to improve patient care and biomedical knowledge. Given this potential, the ethical question arises whether physicians have a professional duty to support SeConts. To investigate this question, we analyze prominent international declarations on physicians' professional ethics to determine whether they include duties that can be considered as good reasons for a physicians' professional duty to support SeConts. Next, we examine these documents to identify professional duties that might conflict with a potential duty of physicians to support SeConts.


Assuntos
Pesquisa Biomédica , Humanos , Pesquisa Biomédica/ética , Médicos/ética , Obrigações Morais , Ética Médica
3.
Bioethics ; 38(5): 425-430, 2024 Jun.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38518191

RESUMO

Advances in assisted reproductive technologies can give rise to several ethical challenges. One of these challenges occurs when the reproductive desires of two individuals become incompatible and conflict. To address such conflicts, it is important to unbundle different aspects of (non)parenthood and to recognize the corresponding reproductive rights. This article starts on the premise that the six reproductive rights-the right (not) to be a gestational, genetic, and social parent-are negative rights that do not entail a right to assistance. Since terminating or continuing a pregnancy is a form of assistance, the right (not) to be a gestational parent should enjoy primacy in conflicts. However, while refusing assistance may hinder the reproductive project of another person, "prior assistance" does not entitle someone to violate a reproductive right. Therefore, our analysis provides reasons to argue that someone has a right to unilaterally use cryopreserved embryos or continue the development of an entity in an extracorporeal gestative environment (i.e., ectogestation). Although this could lead to a violation of the right not to be a genetic parent, it does not necessarily entail a violation of the right not to be a social parent.


Assuntos
Pais , Direitos Sexuais e Reprodutivos , Técnicas de Reprodução Assistida , Humanos , Direitos Sexuais e Reprodutivos/ética , Feminino , Gravidez , Técnicas de Reprodução Assistida/ética , Criopreservação/ética , Ectogênese/ética , Conflito de Interesses
4.
Crit Rev Int Soc Political Philos ; 27(3): 317-338, 2024.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38533485

RESUMO

Corporations wield power in today's economies, and political theories of the corporation argue about the legitimacy conditions of corporate power. This paper argues in favour of a double-fiduciary theory for corporations. Based on a concession theory of markets, it sees all markets as authorized by states (in the name of society), for the purpose of creating economic value, or wealth. Hence corporations, as much as non-incorporated firms, have a fiduciary duty to the state/society to create wealth, in the competitive structure of the market. However, their pursuit of wealth often creates unbalanced relations of power between corporations and their stakeholders, which can at some point be classified as instances of domination. Therefore, corporations need to be subjected to a second fiduciary duty, i.e. not to dominate others in the economy. This duty is also, in the final instance, owed to the state/society. In an era when everyone can incorporate their business, states/societies can be interpreted as having, through corporate law, mandated shareholders as 'proximate beneficiaries', to incentivize corporations to create wealth. Now states/societies need to think about how to prevent corporations from dominating others. New mechanisms of accountability towards stakeholders and/or citizens as proximate beneficiaries are needed. Only in this way can corporations be effectively held to account for both of the fiduciary duties which characterize their normative status.

5.
Work ; 77(4): 1235-1244, 2024.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38339950

RESUMO

BACKGROUND: Within individual policing organisations, there are a wide variety of units and job roles. OBJECTIVE: To profile the occupational tasks performed by Australian mounted police officers, aiming to offer conditioning insight into this unique job role. METHODS: Thirteen fully qualified and operational mounted police officers (n = 11 females), who served in the mounted police unit for ∼3.3 (±2.3) years, participated in this observational cohort study. Participants completed a survey outlining common occupational tasks and were monitored throughout four consecutive shifts. Participants' heart rate (HR), respiratory rate (RR), and skin temperature (ST) data were collected via wearable monitoring (Equivital EQ-02, Hidalgo, UK) and body position, physical activity undertaken, task effort, and load carriage were recorded by researchers. A one-way ANOVA was used to assess mean differences in physiological measures between the three most reported tasks. RESULTS: Survey identified 130 tasks, with 38 listed as most common. The three most reported mounted police tasks were: 'horse riding' (n = 13, 34%), 'mounted patrols' (n = 10, 26%), and 'horse care' (n = 10, 26%). These were also reported as the most physically demanding. HR during 'horse care' and 'horse riding' were significantly higher than when 'mounted patrolling' (27±7bpm, p = 0.001 and 33±8bpm; p = 0.001, respectively). Mean RR was higher when 'horse riding' when compared to 'horse care' (5.3±1.6brpm) and 'mounted patrol' (8.5±1.9brpm). CONCLUSION: Mounted police officers experience unique physiological challenges throughout their routine occupational tasks. This study highlights the significance of understanding occupation-specific tasks and stressors undertaken by mounted police to develop relevant conditioning, rehabilitation, and monitoring procedures.


Assuntos
Ocupações , Polícia , Feminino , Humanos , Austrália , Estudos de Coortes , Inquéritos e Questionários
6.
BMC Public Health ; 24(1): 563, 2024 Feb 22.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38388881

RESUMO

BACKGROUND: Globally, close to one-third of all workplace violence (WV) occurs in the health sector. Exposure to WV among healthcare professionals in Ghana has been widely speculated, but there is limited evidence on the problem. This study therefore investigated WV, its risk factors, and the psychological consequences experienced by health workers in Ghana. METHODS: An analytic cross-sectional study was conducted in the Greater Accra region from January 30 to May 31, 2023, involving selected health facilities. The participants for the study were selected using a simple random sampling technique based on probability proportional-to-size. The data analyses were performed using STATA 15 software. Logistic regression analyses were employed to identify the factors associated with WV, considering a significance level of p-value < 0.05. RESULTS: The study was conducted among 607 healthcare providers and support personnel across 10 public and private hospitals. The lifetime career, and one-year exposure to any form of WV was 414 (68.2%) [95% CI: (64.3-71.9%)] and 363 (59.8%) [95% CI: (55.8-63.7%)], respectively. Compared to other forms of WV, the majority of healthcare workers, 324 (53.4%) experienced verbal abuse within the past year, and a greater proportion, 85 (26.2%) became 'super alert' or vigilant and watchful following incidents of verbal abuse. Factors significantly linked to experiencing any form of WV in the previous 12 months were identified as follows: older age [AOR = 1.11 (1.06, 1.17)], working experience [AOR = 0.91 (0.86, 0.96)], having on-call responsibilities [AOR = 1.75 (1.17, 2.61)], and feeling adequately secure within health facility [AOR = 0.45 (0.26, 0.76)]. CONCLUSION: There was high occurrence of WV, and verbal abuse was the most experienced form of WV. Age, work experience, on-call duties, and security within workplace were associated with exposure to WV. Facility-based interventions are urgently needed to curb the incidence of WV, especially verbal abuse.


Assuntos
Violência no Trabalho , Humanos , Violência no Trabalho/psicologia , Estudos Transversais , Gana/epidemiologia , Prevalência , Inquéritos e Questionários , Pessoal de Saúde/psicologia , Local de Trabalho/psicologia , Fatores de Risco
7.
Am J Infect Control ; 52(3): 365-367, 2024 Mar.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38036177

RESUMO

Although critical access hospitals are small, the expected infection prevention activities remain extensive. Program standards, aligned with the Association for Professionals in Infection Control and Epidemiology infection prevention competency model domains, were developed and implemented in a midwestern health care system. Time estimates for completion of each activity were assigned and then extrapolated to offer guidance on necessary full-time equivalents for adequate staffing.


Assuntos
Atenção à Saúde , Controle de Infecções , Humanos , Recursos Humanos , Estudantes , Hospitais , Desenvolvimento de Programas
8.
Theor Med Bioeth ; 45(1): 5-23, 2024 Feb.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37979016

RESUMO

The Harm Threshold (HT) holds that the state may interfere in medical decisions parents make on their children's behalf only when those decisions are likely to cause serious harm to the child. Such a high bar for intervention seems incompatible with both parental obligations and the state's role in protecting children's well-being. In this paper, I assess the theoretical underpinnings for the HT, focusing on John Stuart Mill's Harm Principle as its most plausible conceptual foundation. I offer (i) a novel, text-based argument showing that Mill's Harm Principle does not give justificatory force to the HT; and (ii) a positive account of some considerations which, beyond significant harm, would comprise an intervention principle normatively grounded in Mill's ethical theory. I find that substantive recommendations derived from Mill's socio-political texts are less laissez-faire than they have been interpreted by HT proponents. Justification for state intervention owes not to the severity of a harm, but to whether that harm arises from the failure to satisfy one's duty. Thus, a pediatric intervention principle derived from Mill ought not to be oriented around the degree of harm caused by a parent's healthcare decision, but rather, the kind of harm-specifically, whether the harm arises from violation of parental obligation. These findings challenge the interpretation of Mill adopted by HT proponents, eliminating a critical source of justification for a protected domain of parental liberty and reorienting the debate to focus on parental duties.


Assuntos
Dissidências e Disputas , Pais , Criança , Humanos , Liberdade , Teoria Ética
10.
MMW Fortschr Med ; 165(14): 43-45, 2023 08.
Artigo em Alemão | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37537461

RESUMO

With the latest amendment of the guardianship law the German legislator means to strengthen the patients' right of self-determination. The most significant new regulations are the introduction of mutual legal representation of married couples in emergency and changes restricting the guardian's legal position. New challenges for doctors and lawyers arise especially from the legal representation of married couples. General practitioners who advise their patients with the preparation of provision documents should particularly explain the importance of recordations in the central providing register (ZVR).


Assuntos
Clínicos Gerais , Tutores Legais , Humanos , Pacientes
11.
Belitung Nurs J ; 9(2): 145-151, 2023.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37469589

RESUMO

Background: The Infection Prevention and Control Nurse (IPCN) is a professional nurse with a crucial role in promoting patient safety and service quality by preventing and controlling infections. However, little is known about their experiences regarding their roles and duties, particularly in Indonesia. Objective: This study aimed to explore IPCNs' experiences in performing their roles and responsibilities, including motivations and obstacles encountered, as well as organizational support while carrying out their jobs. Methods: This research used a qualitative descriptive study design, collecting data through Focus Group Discussions (FGDs) with six purposively sampled participants in April 2021 at the Gatot Soebroto Army Central Hospital (RSPAD), Jakarta, Indonesia. Thematic analysis was used to analyze the data. Results: Five themes were identified: 1) roles and duties of IPCNs, 2) conducive work environment, 3) constraints in carrying out tasks, 4) management support, and 5) hopes. Conclusion: This study provides new insights into IPCN roles and duties that require collaboration and coordination with multiple professions, as well as management support to overcome obstacles that hinder fulfilling tasks and hopes of improving IPCN performance according to competency-based career paths to achieve patient safety, service quality, and job satisfaction.

12.
Philos Stud ; 180(5-6): 1691-1715, 2023.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37323613

RESUMO

According to some collectivists, purposive groups that lack decision-making procedures such as riot mobs, friends walking together, or the pro-life lobby can be morally responsible and have moral duties. I focus on plural subject- and we-mode-collectivism. I argue that purposive groups do not qualify as duty-bearers even if they qualify as agents on either view. To qualify as a duty-bearer, an agent must be morally competent. I develop the Update Argument. An agent is morally competent only if the agent has sufficient positive and negative control over updating their goal-seeking states. Positive control involves the general ability to update one's goal-seeking states, whereas negative control involves the absence of other agents with the capacity to arbitrarily interfere with updating one's goal-seeking states. I argue that even if purposive groups qualify as plural subjects or we-mode group agents, these groups necessarily lack negative control over updating their goal-seeking states. This creates a cut-off point for groups as duty-bearers: Organized groups may qualify as duty-bearers, whereas purposive groups cannot qualify as duty-bearers.

13.
Rev. bioét. derecho ; (57): 33-51, Mar. 2023. ilus
Artigo em Espanhol | IBECS | ID: ibc-216057

RESUMO

El presente artículo analiza la responsabilidad civil médica atribuible a los profesionales de la salud que intervienen en el proceso de atención a distancia. Con este objeto, se propone un conjunto de principios de los cuales se derivan deberes de cuidado en la telemedicina exigibles a los profesionales de salud y a los prestadores. A partir de los principios de analogía con y complementariedad de la atención presencial, se desarrollan tres categorías de principios especiales para la atención a distancia: principios habilitantes, principios operativos y principios de protección al paciente. Bajo este esquema de principios se especifican deberes de cuidado, distinguiendo aquellos que responden a los riesgos causados por la distancia física de aquellos que surgen de los cambios organizacionales necesarios para este tipo de atención. La aplicación de estos deberes se analiza en tres escenarios de telemedicina: la teleconsulta, la teleinterconsulta y la teleconsultoría. Esta estructura de principios y deberes en la prestación de salud a distancia permite delimitar los alcances de la lex artis para cada escenario específico y, al mismo tiempo, elaborar estrategias regulatorias considerando criterios de necesidad, racionalidad y suficiencia, según los contenidos específicos que caracterizan cada escenario de atención de salud a distancia. (AU)


El present article analitza la responsabilitat civil mèdica atribuïble als professionals de la salut que intervenen en el procés d'atenció a distància. Amb aquest objecte, es proposa un conjunt de principis dels quals es deriven deures de cura en la telemedicina exigibles als professionals de salut i als prestadors. A partir delsprincipis d'analogia amb i complementarietat de l'atenció presencial, es desenvolupen tres categories de principis especials per a l'atenció a distància: principis habilitants, principis operatius i principis de protecció al pacient. Sota aquest esquema de principis s'especifiquen deures de cura, distingint aquells que responen als riscos causats per la distància física d'aquells que sorgeixen dels canvis organitzacionals necessaris per a aquesta mena d'atenció. L'aplicació d'aquests deures s'analitza en tres escenaris de telemedicina: la teleconsulta, la teleinterconsulta i la teleconsultoría. Aquesta estructura de principis i deures en la prestació de salut a distància permet delimitar els abastos de la lex artis per a cada escenari específic i, al mateixtemps, elaborar estratègies reguladores considerant criteris de necessitat, racionalitat i suficiència, segons els continguts específics que caracteritzen cada escenari d'atenció de salut a distància.(AU)


This article analyzes the civil medical liability imputable to health professionals involved at remote healthcare. To this end, a set of principles is proposed from which health professionals and telemedicine providers are required to perform care duties. Based on the principles of analogy with and complementarity of face-to-face healthcare, three categories of special principles for remote healthcare are developed: enabling principles, operational principles, and patient protection principles. Under this scheme of principles, duties of care are specified, distinguishing those that respond to the risks caused by physical distance from those that arise from the organizational changes necessary for this type of healthcare. The application of these duties is analyzed in three telemedicine scenarios: virtual visit, virtual consult and eConsult. This structure of principles and duties in the provision of remote healthcare allows to delimit the scope of leges artis for each specific scenario and, at the same time, to develop regulatory strategies considering criteria of necessity, rationality and sufficiency, according to the specific contents that characterize each scenario of remote healthcare.(AU)


Assuntos
Humanos , Responsabilidade Civil , Telemedicina , Pessoal de Saúde , Princípios Morais , Responsabilidade Legal , Bioética , Temas Bioéticos
14.
Gynecol Obstet Fertil Senol ; 51(4): 212-216, 2023 04.
Artigo em Francês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36736780

RESUMO

The right to consent has become over time a fundamental right in both French and international law. Even if it is not formalized, the patient's consent is now required for each medical act. Moreover, it is always revocable. This article proposes to outline the historical evolution of consent in French legal texts.


Assuntos
Consentimento Livre e Esclarecido , Humanos
15.
Am J Bioeth ; 23(8): 22-32, 2023 Aug.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36449269

RESUMO

Clinicians have good moral and professional reasons to contribute to pragmatic clinical trials (PCTs). We argue that clinicians have a defeasible duty to participate in this research that takes place in usual care settings and does not involve substantive deviation from their ordinary care practices. However, a variety of countervailing reasons may excuse clinicians from this duty in particular cases. Yet because there is a moral default in favor of participating, clinicians who wish to opt out of this research must justify their refusal. Reasons to refuse include that the trial is badly designed in some way, that the trial activities will violate the clinician's conscience, or that the trial will impose excessive burdens on the clinician.


Assuntos
Princípios Morais , Ensaios Clínicos Pragmáticos como Assunto , Humanos , Consciência , Recusa em Tratar
16.
J Law Med ; 30(2): 345-357, 2023 Jul.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38303619

RESUMO

A key function of clinical ethics services (CESs) is to provide decision-making support to health care providers in ethically challenging cases. Cases referred for ethics consultation are likely to involve diverging views or conflict, or to confront the boundaries of appropriate medical practice. Such cases might also attract legal action due to their contentious nature. As CESs become more prevalent in Australia, this article considers the potential legal liability of a CES and its members. With no reported litigation against a CES in Australia, we look to international experience and first principles. We consider the prospects of a claim in negligence, the most likely legal action against a CES, through application of legal principles to a hypothetical case scenario. We conclude that, although unlikely to be successful at this time, a CES could face answerable claims in negligence brought by patients (and families) who are the subject of ethics case consultation.


Assuntos
Ética Clínica , Imperícia , Humanos , Responsabilidade Legal , Austrália
17.
J Med Philos ; 47(6): 701-710, 2022 12 23.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36562837

RESUMO

Recent works on the concept of dignity have opened up the otherwise quite deadlocked debate about assisted death (AD). Rather than just reinforcing already fixed positions, it seems to me that these conceptions of dignity make room for a moderate and normatively richer position on the moral permissibility of AD. I do not think that we have seen the full potential of the said conceptions and interpretations. I try in this article to contribute my part. First, I briefly recapitulate some of the paradoxical ways in which dignity is typically invoked in the debate and try to clear up some of the obvious confusions. Then, I go on to explore a particular Kantian line of thought in some recent works on dignity and AD that seems to pave the way for a moderate position with a more principled foundation than the usual compromise positions.


Assuntos
Suicídio Assistido , Humanos , Respeito , Princípios Morais
18.
Nutrients ; 14(22)2022 Nov 19.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36432590

RESUMO

COVID-19's intimidating spread has challenged the resilience of the global health systems, causing shifts in the practices of healthcare workers, including dietitians. The current study aimed to assess the change in dietitians' practices and duties in hospitals/clinics after the commencement of COVID-19 pandemic. This cross-sectional study was conducted in five Arab countries between November 2020 and January 2021. A convenient sample of 903 dietitians filled an online self-administered questionnaire to meet the study aims. Nearly 40.0% of the dietitians experienced a change in their workload and caseload during the pandemic. Besides, 18.7% of the dietitians had been assigned additional tasks in their facilities. Nearly half the dietitians (46.9%) had started giving remote nutrition consultations, associated with a 21% drop in the number of dietitians offering in-person consultations (p = 0.001). Approximately 58.9% of the dietitians provided nutrition care to COVID-19 patients, with 48.4% having access to personal protective equipment. Moreover, 17.0% of dietitians supported COVID-19 patients with enteral and parenteral nutrition. In addition, 45.0% of dietitians reported that managing COVID-19 was challenging given that it was a newly discovered condition.


Assuntos
COVID-19 , Dietética , Nutricionistas , Humanos , Estudos Transversais , COVID-19/epidemiologia , Pandemias , Árabes
19.
Ethical Theory Moral Pract ; : 1-15, 2022 Nov 02.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36339916

RESUMO

Are corporations ever morally obligated to engage in counterspeech-that is, in speech that aims to counter hate speech and misinformation? While existing arguments in moral and political philosophy show that individuals and states have such obligations, it is an open question whether those arguments apply to corporations as well. In this essay, I show how two such arguments-one based on avoiding complicity, and one based on duties of rescue-can plausibly be extended to corporations. I also respond to several objections to corporate counterspeech.

20.
Rev. bioét. derecho ; (56): 55-74, Nov. 2022.
Artigo em Inglês | IBECS | ID: ibc-210237

RESUMO

Gestational surrogacy is a controversial ethical issue worldwide. In 2016, Portugal launched a second political attempt to legalize gestational surrogacy, proposing it as: being altruistic; forbidding a biological tie between the surrogate and the child; requiring a biological relationship between one of the legal parents and the child; and demanding a legal contract between the surrogate and the legal parents. The law was approved, regulatedand entered into force. However, months later, the Constitutional Court ruled some of its norms unconstitutional, namely due tothe legal ambiguity of the surrogacy contracts; too short a deadline for the surrogate’s withdraw of consent; and the need to comply with the children’s right to know their biological origin. The law entered a complex political and legal process. It also caused a serious problem in assisted reproductive treatments, with the suspension of those treatments that entailed the anonymity of the donors. The law on surrogacy was, finally, enacted in November 2021, although the introduction of its regulation is still pending.This paper describes the legal process, within its political context, stressing the ethical issues at stake, and presenting the initiative for legalization of gestational surrogacy in Portugal as a valuable case study analysis: of how a top-down initiative, ideologically driven and politically rushed, and which ignores ethical advice, generates a troubled and penalizinglegal process for the people involved.(AU)


La gestació subrogada és una qüestió ètica controvertida a tot el món. En 2016, Portugal va llançar un segon intent polític per a legalitzar la subrogació gestacional, proposant-la com: altruista; prohibint un vincle biològic entre la subrogada i el nen; exigint una relació biològica entre un dels pares legals i el nen; i exigint un contracte legal entre la subrogada i els pares legals. La llei va ser aprovada, reglamentada i va entrar en vigor. No obstant, mesos després, el Tribunal Constitucional va dictaminar la inconstitucionalitat d'algunes de les seves normes, en concret: l'ambigüitat jurídica dels contractes de gestació subrogada; un termini massa curt per a la retirada del consentiment de la mare de lloguer; i la necessitat de complir amb el dret dels nens a conèixer el seu origen biològic. La llei va entrar en un complex procés polític i jurídic. També va provocar un greu problema en els tractaments de reproducció assistida, amb la suspensió d'aquells que implicaven l'anonimat de les donants. La llei de gestació subrogada va ser, finalment, promulgada al novembre de 2021, si bé encara està pendent la introducció del seu reglament. Aquest treball descriu el procés legal, dins del seu context polític, posant l'accent en les qüestions ètiques en joc, i presentant aquesta iniciativa com una valuosa anàlisi de cas: de com una iniciativa de dalt a baix, ideològicament impulsada i políticament precipitada, i que ignora l'assessorament ètic, genera un procés legal problemàtic i penalitzador per a les persones implicades.(AU)


La gestación subrogada es una cuestión ética controvertida en todo el mundo. En 2016, Portugal lanzó un segundo intento político para legalizar la subrogación gestacional, proponiéndola como: altruista; prohibiendo un vínculo biológico entre la subrogada y el niño; exigiendo una relación biológica entre uno de los padres legales y el niño; y exigiendo un contrato legal entre la subrogada y los padres legales. La ley fue aprobada, reglamentada y entró en vigor. Sin embargo, meses después, el Tribunal Constitucional dictaminó la inconstitucionalidad de algunas de sus normas, en concreto: la ambigüedad jurídica de los contratos de gestación subrogada; un plazo demasiado corto para la retirada del consentimiento de la madre de alquiler; y la necesidad de cumplir con el derecho de los niños a conocer su origen biológico. La ley entró en un complejo proceso político y jurídico. También provocó un grave problema en los tratamientos de reproducción asistida, con la suspensión de aquellos que implicaban el anonimato de las donantes. La ley de gestación subrogada fue, finalmente, promulgada en noviembre de 2021, aunque aún está pendiente la introducción de su reglamento. Este trabajo describe el proceso legal, dentro de su contexto político, haciendo hincapié en las cuestiones éticas que están en juego, y presentando la iniciativa de legalización de la gestación subrogada en Portugal como un valioso análisis de caso: de cómo una iniciativa de arriba abajo, ideológicamente impulsada y políticamente precipitada, y que ignora el asesoramiento ético, genera un proceso legal problemático y penalizador para las personas implicadas.(AU)


Assuntos
Humanos , Gravidez , Mães Substitutas , Política de Saúde , Técnicas Reprodutivas , Consentimento Livre e Esclarecido , Direitos Sexuais e Reprodutivos , Poder Familiar , Jurisprudência , Portugal , Bioética , Ética , Direitos Humanos , Princípios Morais
SELEÇÃO DE REFERÊNCIAS
DETALHE DA PESQUISA
...